|
Introduction: Remarks on Chauvinism and the Mind-Body Problem Sample Chapter - Download PDF (67 KB) |
1 | |
I | Functionalism | 13 |
1 | Functionalism Sample Chapter - Download PDF (73 KB) |
15 |
2 | What Is Functionalism? | 27 |
3 | What Psychological States Are Not, with J. Fodor | 45 |
4 | Troubles with Functionalism | 63 |
5 | What Intuitions about Homunculi Do Not Show | 103 |
II | Concepts of Consciousness | 109 |
6 | Consciousness | 111 |
7 | Review of Daniel Dennett, Consciousness Explained | 129 |
8 | What Is Dennett's Theory a Theory Of? | 141 |
9 | On a Confusion about a Function of Consciousness | 159 |
10 | How Many Concepts of Consciousness? | 215 |
11 | Biology versus Computation in the Study of Consciousness | 249 |
12 | Ridiculing Social Constructivism about Phenomenal Consciousness | 269 |
13 | Concepts of Consciousness | 275 |
III | Empirical Approaches to Consciousness | 297 |
14 | How Not to Find the Neural Correlate of Consciousness | 299 |
15 | Paradox and Cross-Purposes in Recent Work on Consciousness | 311 |
16 | Spatial Perception via Tactile Sensation | 339 |
17 | Two Neural Correlates of Consciousness | 343 |
18 | Review of Alva Noe, Action in Perception | 363 |
IV | Consciousness and the Mind-Body Problem | 377 |
19 | Are Absent Qualia Impossible? | 379 |
20 | The Harder Problem of Consciousness | 397 |
21 | Max Black's Objection to Mind-Body Identity | 435 |
V | Consciousness and Representation | 499 |
22 | Qualia | 501 |
23 | Inverted Earth | 511 |
24 | Mental Paint | 533 |
25 | Sexism, Racism, Ageism, and the Nature of Consciousness | 571 |
26 | Is Experiencing Just Representing? | 603 |
27 | Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism | 611 |
Name Index Sample Chapter - Download PDF (33 KB) |
617 | |
Subject Index
|
http://mitpress.mit.edu/catalog/item/default.asp?ttype=2&tid=11055&mode=toc
◈ Block, Ned Joel (forthcoming, available online Mar. 12, 2007). Consciousness, Accessibility, and the Mesh between Psychology and Neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences.
How can we disentangle the neural basis of phenomenal consciousness from the neural machinery of the cognitive access that underlies reports of phenomenal consciousness? We can see the problem in stark form if we ask how we could tell whether representations inside a Fodorian module are phenomenally conscious. The methodology would seem straightforward: find the neural natural kinds that are the basis of phenomenal consciousness in clear cases when subjects are completely confident and we have no reason to doubt their authority, and look to see whether those neural natural kinds exist within Fodorian modules. But a puzzle arises: do we include the machinery underlying reportability within the neural natural kinds of the clear cases? If the answer is ‘Yes’, then there can be no phenomenally conscious representations in Fodorian modules. But how can we know if the answer is ‘Yes’? The suggested methodology requires an answer to the question it was supposed to answer! The paper argues for an abstract solution to the problem and exhibits a source of empirical data that is relevant, data that show that in a certain sense phenomenal consciousness overflows cognitive accessibility. The paper argues that we can find a neural realizer of this overflow if assume that the neural basis of phenomenal consciousness does not include the neural basis of cognitive accessibility and that this assumption is justified (other things equal) by the explanations it allows.
http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/puzzle.pdf
◈ Block, Ned Joel (forthcoming, available online Mar. 12, 2007). Wittgenstein and Qualia. Philosophical Perspectives edited by John Hawthorne.
In the “Notes for Lectures on “Private Experience” and “Sense Data”” (published in 1968), Wittgenstein endorsed one kind of inverted spectrum hypothesis and rejected another. This paper argues that the kind of inverted spectrum hypothesis that Wittgenstein endorsed (the “innocuous” inverted spectrum hypothesis) is the thin end of the wedge that precludes a Wittgensteinian critique of the kind of inverted spectrum hypothesis he rejected (the “dangerous” kind). I will attempt to explicate the difference between the innocuous and dangerous scenarios, to give arguments in favor of the coherence of the dangerous scenario, and to show that the standard arguments to the effect that the dangerous scenario is impossible are flawed or ineffective against the version of the dangerous scenario whose coherence I will be advocating. I will also agree with what I think is Wittgenstein’s position that the kind of inverted spectrum hypothesis he rejected lets qualia in the door, where qualia are (for the purposes of this paper) qualities of experiential states whose phenomenal character cannot be expressed in natural language. Further, I will argue that acknowledging the coherence of the innocuous inverted spectrum commits Wittgenstein to the coherence of the dangerous inverted spectrum, thereby undermining Wittgenstein’s deepest views about the mind. In other work, I have used the inverted spectrum hypothesis as an argument against functionalism and representationism, but here the focus is on its role in arguing for the possibility of qualia.
http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/Wittgenstein_Qualia.pdf
▣ Bontly, Thomas D. (2002). The Supervenience Argument Generalizes. Philosopical Studies 109(1): 75–96.
Abstract: In his recent book, Jaegwon Kim argues thatpsychophysical supervenience withoutpsychophysical reduction renders mentalcausation `unintelligible'. He also claimsthat, contrary to popular opinion, his argumentagainst supervenient mental causation cannot begeneralized so as to threaten the causalefficacy of other `higher-level' properties:e.g., the properties of special sciences likebiology. In this paper, I argue that none ofthe considerations Kim advances are sufficientto keep the supervenience argument fromgeneralizing to all higher-level properties,and that Kim's position in fact entails thatonly the properties of fundamental physicalparticles are causally efficacious.
◇ Boogerd, Fred C., Frank J. Bruggeman, Jan-Hendrik S. Hofmeyr and Hans V. Westerhoff (eds.) (Apr. 2007). Systems Biology: Philosophical Foundations. Amsterdam, The Netherlands/Oxford, Uk: Elsevier Science.
Description
Systems biology is a vigorous and expanding discipline, in many ways a successor to genomics and perhaps unprecedented in its combination of biology with a great many other sciences, from physics to ecology, from mathematics to medicine, and from philosophy to chemistry. Studying the philosophical foundations of systems biology may resolve a longer standing issue, i.e., the extent to which Biology is entitled to its own scientific foundations rather than being dominated by existing philosophies.
Table of contents
List of Contributors.....vii
Contributor Biographies.....ix
Preface.....xvii
Section I Introduction.....1
1. Towards philosophical foundations of Systems Biology: Introduction.....F.C. Boogerd, F.J. Bruggeman, J.-H.S. Hofmeyr and H.V. Westerhoff.....3
Section II Research programs of Systems Biology.....21
2. The methodologies of Systems Biology.....H.V. Westerhoff and D.B. Kell.....23
3. Methodology is Philosophy.....R.G. Shulman.....71
4. How can we understand metabolism?.....D.A. Fell......87
5. On Building Reliable Pictures with Unreliable Data: an Evolutionary and Developmental Coda for the New Systems Biology?.....W.C. Wimsatt.....103
Section III Theory / models.....121
6. Mechanism and mechanical explanation in cell biology.....R.C. Richardson and A. Stephan.....123
7. Theories, Models, and Equations in Systems Biology.....K.F. Schaffner.....145
8. All models are wrong...some more than others.....O. Wolkenhauer and M. Ullah.....163
9. Data without models merging with models without data.....U. Krohs and W. Callebaut.....181
Section IV Organization in biological systems.....215
10. The biochemical factory that autonomously fabricates itself: a systems-biological view of the living cell.....J.-H.S. Hofmeyr.....217
11. A systemic approach to the origin of biological organization.....A. Moreno.....243
12. Organization and biological mechanisms: organized to maintain autonomy.....W. Bechtel.....269
13. The disappearance of function from 'self-organizing systems'.....E.F. Keller.....303
Section V Conclusion.....319
14. Afterthoughts as foundations for Systems Biology.....F.C. Boogerd, F.J. Bruggeman, J.-H.S. Hofmeyr and H.V. Westerhoff.....321
Subject Index.....337
◈ Boogerd, Fred C., Frank J. Bruggeman, Robert C. Richardson, Achim Stephan, and Hans V. Westerhoff (2005). Emergence and its Place in Nature: a case study of biochemical networks. Synthese 145: 131–164.
http://www.cogsci.uni-osnabrueck.de/~acstepha/Emergence_Place_Nature_Synthese (2005).pdf
◈ Boschetti, F., M. Prokopenko, I. Macreadie, A.M. Grisogono (2005). Defining and detecting emergence in complex networks. Knowledge-based Intelligent Information and Engineering Systems, PT 4, Proceedings Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence 3684: 573-580.
Abstract: Emergence is seen as the most significant feature discriminating "complex" from "non complex" systems. Nevertheless, no standard definition of emergence is currently available in the literature. This lack of a shared view affects the development of tools to detect and model emergence for both scientific and engineering applications. Here we review some definitions of emergence with the aim to describe how they can be implemented in algorithms to detect and model emergence in sensor and communication networks.
▣ Boyd, R. (1980). Materialism without reductionism: What physicalism does not entail. In: Ned Joel Block (ed.) Readings in Philosophy of Psychology. Vol. 1. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, pp. 67-106.
◈ Bratcher, Daniel (Fall, 1999). David Chalmers' arguments for "property dualism". Philosophy Today: 292-301.
◇ Bregant, Janez (2004). Van Gulick’s Solution of the Exclusion Problem Revisited. Acta Analytica 19(33):
Abstract: The anti-reductionist who wants to preserve the causal efficacy of mental phenomena faces several problems in regard to mental causation, i.e. mental events which cause other events, arising from her desire to accept the ontological primacy of the physical and at the same time save the special character of the mental. Psychology tries to persuade us of the former, appealing thereby to the results of experiments carried out in neurology; the latter is, however, deeply rooted in our everyday actions and beliefs and despite the constant opposition of science still very much alive. Difficulties, however, arise from a combination of two claims that are widely accepted in philosophy of mind, namely, physical monism and mental realism, the acceptance of which leads us to the greatest problem of mental causation: the problem of causal exclusion. Since physical causes alone are always sufficient for physical effect mental properties are excluded from causal explanations of our behaviour, which makes them “epiphenomenal”. The article introduces Van Gulick’s solution to the exclusion problem and my objection to it.
◈ Broad, C.D. (1925). The Mind and Its Place in Nature. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. first edition.
Charlie Dunbar Broad (1887―1971)
Ditext reprint available online http://www.ditext.com/broad/mpn/mpn.html
◈ Brooks, Rodney (Jan. 2001). The relationship between matter and life. Nature 409: 409-411.
◈ Brown, Richard (Dec. 2006). What Is a Brain State? Philosophical Psychology 19(6): 729-742.
Abstract: Philosophers have been talking about brain states for almost 50 years and as of yet no one has articulated a theoretical account of what one is. In fact this issue has received almost no attention and cognitive scientists still use meaningless phrases like 'C-fiber firing' and 'neuronal activity' when theorizing about the relation of the mind to the brain. To date when theorists do discuss brain states they usually do so in the context of making some other argument with the result being that any discussion of what brain states are has a distinct en passant flavor. In light of this it is a goal of mine to make brain states the center of attention by providing some general discussion of them. I briefly look at the argument of Bechtel and Mundale, as I think that they expose a common misconception philosophers had about brain states early on. I then turn to briefly examining Polger's argument, as I think he offers an intuitive account of what we expect brain states to be as well as a convincing argument against a common candidate for knowledge about brain states that is currently "on the scene." I then introduce a distinction between brain states and states of the brain: Particular brain states occur against background states of the brain. I argue that brain states are patterns of synchronous neural firing, which reflects the electrical face of the brain; states of the brain are the gating and modulating of neural activity and reflect the chemical face of the brain.
Keywords: Brain State; Identity Conditions; Identity Theory; Mind-Body Problem; Single Cell Recording
◈ Brüntrup, Godehard (1998). Is psycho-physical emergentism committed to dualism?: the causal efficacy of emergent mental properties. Erkenntnis Vol. 48, Iss. 2/3: 133-151.
▣ Bunge, Mario Augusto (1977). Emergence and the mind. Neuroscience 2(4): 501-509.
◈ Bunge, Mario Augusto (1977). Levels and reduction. American Journal of Physiology 233(3): R75-R82.
◈ Bunge, Mario Augusto (2003). Emergence and Convergence: Qualitative Novelty and the Unity of Knowledge. University of Toronto Press.
◆ Bünning, Silvia and Olaf Blanke (2005). The out-of body experience: precipitating factors and neural correlates. Progress in Brain Research 150: 331-350, 605-606.
Available online 25 September 2005.
Abstract: Out-of-body experiences (OBEs) are defined as experiences in which a person seems to be awake and sees his body and the world from a location outside his physical body. More precisely, they can be defined by the presence of the following three phenomenological characteristics: (i) disembodiment (location of the self outside one's body); (ii) the impression of seeing the world from an elevated and distanced visuo-spatial perspective (extracorporeal, but egocentric visuo-spatial perspective); and (iii) the impression of seeing one's own body (autoscopy) from this perspective. OBEs have fascinated mankind from time immemorial and are abundant in folklore, mythology, and spiritual experiences of most ancient and modern societies. Here, we review some of the classical precipitating factors of OBEs such as sleep, drug abuse, and general anesthesia as well as their neurobiology and compare them with recent findings on neurological and neurocognitive mechanisms of OBEs. The reviewed data suggest that OBEs are due to functional disintegration of lower-level multisensory processing and abnormal higher-level self-processing at the temporo-parietal junction. We argue that the experimental investigation of the interactions between these multisensory and cognitive mechanisms in OBEs and related illusions in combination with neuroimaging and behavioral techniques might further our understanding of the central mechanisms of corporal awareness and self-consciousness much as previous research about the neural bases of complex body part illusions such as phantom limbs has done.
◇ Burkhardt , Hans, Johanna Seibt and Guido Imaguire (eds.) (forthcoming, Oct. 2007). Handbook of Mereology. München: Philosophia Verlag.
Mereology is the investigation of part-whole relationships within all domains of reality and conceptualisation. Research in mereology has a long history and a high degree of theoretical articulation yet still lacks a synoptic presentation. The Handbook of Mereology collects international research in this fundamental philosophical discipline in a comprehensive volume, treating a wide range of issues in theoretical mereology, applied mereology and history of mereology. For the first time the Handbook presents mereology as an integrated field of research relevant to scholars working in widely different disciplines such as ontology, metaphysics, logic, philosophy of mind, semantics, linguistics, and knowledge representation. Addressing both specialists and interested readers it aims to serve both as a reference work as well as a systematic introduction to a field with increasing relevance in analytic philosophy.
Following the format of the Handbook of Metaphysics and Ontology, this volume will contain more than 250 articles on specific themes and research results in mereology, together with biographical essays summarizing historical contributions to the field. All articles have been specially commissioned for this work from leading authorities on the respective issues. The contributions are ordered alphabetically, yet survey articles with embedded subarticles and special attention to cross references highlight systematic connections. Each article is followed by a short list of recommended further readings. In addition the book includes the most comprehensive bibliography on mereology up-to-date.
◈ Buzsáki, György (Oct. 2006). Rhythms of the Brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◈ Buzsáki, György (2007). The structure of consciousness. Nature 446: 267-267 (Issue of 15 Mar 2007).
Subjective awareness may depend on neural networks in the brain supporting complex wiring schemes and dynamic patterns of activity.
◈ Campbell, Donald T. (1974). Downward Causation in Hierarchically Organised Biological Systems. Published pp. 179-186 in: Francisco J. Ayala & Theodosius Grigorevich Dobzhansky (eds.) Studies in the Philosophy of Biology: Reduction and Related Problems. Berkeley: University of California Press.
◈ Carrier, Martin (2003). Emergence and the Final Theory, or: How to make Scientific Progress Sustainable. Revista de Filosofia 28(1): 7-31.
http://fs-morente.filos.ucm.es/publicaciones/revista/vol28n1/carrier.pdf
◇ Carrier, Martin and Patrick Finzer (Oct. 2006). Explanatory Loops and the Limits of Genetic Reductionism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 20(3): 267-283. (DOI: 10.1080/02698590600960937)
Abstract: We reconstruct genetic determinism as a reductionist thesis to the effect that the molecular properties of cells can be accounted for to a great extent by their genetic outfit. The non-reductionist arguments offered at this molecular level often use the relationship between structure and function as their point of departure. By contrast, we develop a non-reductionist argument that is confined to the structural characteristics of biomolecules; no appeal to functions is made. We raise two kinds of objections against the reducibility claim underlying genetic determinism. First, some conceptual distinctions at the protein level cannot be captured on a genetic basis. A one-to-many relationship between DNA sequences and proteins emerges from them. Second, the relationship between genes and proteins is characterized by explanatory loops or reciprocal explanatory dependence. The presence of proteins is explained by the transcription from corresponding DNA sequences, and the latter is in turn accounted for by the action of proteins. By contrast, a reductive account requires a unidirectional explanatory dependence.
◈ Castellani, Elena (2002). Reductionism, emergence, and effective field theories. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 33: 251-267.
◈ Chakrabarti, Bikas K. and Rahul Banerjee (eds.) (in press). Models of Brain and Mind: Physical, Computational and Psychological Approaches. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
◈ Chalmers, David John (1996). The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. Oxford University Press.
◈ Chalmers, David John (2006). Strong and Weak Emergence. Published in: Clayton, Philip, Paul Davies (eds.) The Re-Emergence of Emergence: The Emergentist Hypothesis from Science to Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◈ Chalmers, David John (Mar. 2008). The Character of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◈ Chomsky, Noam (Mar. 2007). Biolinguistic Explorations: Design, Development, Evolution. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 15(1): 1-21.
Abstract: Biolinguistic inquiry investigates the human language faculty as an internal biological property. This article traces the development of biolinguistics from its early philosophical origins through its reformulation during the cognitive revolution of the 1950s and outlines my views on where the biolinguistic enterprise stands today. The growth of language in the individual, it is suggested, depends on (i) genetic factors, (ii) experience, and (iii) principles that are not specific to the faculty of language. The best current explanation of how language is recursively generated is through Merge, an operation that takes objects already constructed, and reconstructs a new object from them, generating a 'language of thought', perhaps in a manner close to optimal (relying on principles of category (iii)), with externalization (hence communication) a secondary process. The concluding section of the article offers several objectives for future research in the field.
Keywords: biolinguistics; evolution of language; I-language; language of thought; semantic interface; Merge
◈ Clark, Andy (1997) Emergence and Explanation. Chapter 6 of his Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
◈ Clayton, Philip (2004). Mind and Emergence: From Quantum to Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◈ Clayton, Philip (2006). Conceptual Foundations of Emergence Theory. Published pp. 1-31 in: Clayton, Philip, Paul Davies (eds.) The Re-Emergence of Emergence: The Emergentist Hypothesis from Science to Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Available online http://www.oup.co.uk/pdf/0-19-928714-7.pdf
◈ Clayton, Philip and Paul Davies (eds.) (2006). The Re-Emergence of Emergence: The Emergentist Hypothesis from Science to Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
contents
◈ Clayton, Philip and Zachary Simpson (eds.) (2006). The Oxford Handbook of Religion and Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◈ Collier, John D. (1988). Supervenience and Reduction in Biological Hierarchies. In Mohan Matthen and Bernard Linsky (eds.) Philosophy and Biology: Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume 14 (1988): 209-234.
http://www.nu.ac.za/undphil/collier/papers/redsup.pdf
◈ Collier, John D. (2003). Fundamental Properties of Self-Organization. In Vladimir Arshinov and Christian Fuchs (eds.) Causality, Emergence, Self-Organisation (Moscow, NIA-Piroda, 2003): 150-166.
◈ Collier, John D. (2003). Organisation in Biological Systems. In Vladimir Arshinov and Christian Fuchs (eds.) Causality, Emergence, Self-Organisation (Moscow, NIA-Piroda, 2003): 287-302.
◈ Collier, John D. (2004). Reduction, Supervenience, and Physical Emergence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27(5): 629-630.
http://www.ukzn.ac.za/undphil/collier/papers/Commentary%20on%20Don%20Ross.htm
◈ Collier, John D. and Clifford A. Hooker (1999). Complexly Organised Dynamical Systems. Open Systems and Information Dynamics 6(3): 241-302.
http://www.newcastle.edu.au/centre/casrg/publications/Cods.pdf
◈ Collier, John D. and Scott J. Muller (1998). The Dynamical Basis of Emergence in Natural Hierarchies. In George Farre and Tarko Oksala (eds.) Emergence, Complexity, Hierarchy and Organization, Selected and Edited Papers from the ECHO III Conference, Acta Polytechnica Scandinavica, MA91 (Finish Academy of Technology, Espoo, 1998).
http://www.nu.ac.za/undphil/collier/papers/echoiii.pdf
◈ Corning, Peter A. (2002). The Emergence of "Emergence": Now What? Emergence 4(3): 54-71.
◈ Corning, Peter A. (2002). The Re-emergence of "Emergence": A venerable concept in search of a theory (one solution: The "Synergism Hypothesis) Complexity 7(6): 18-30.
◆ Crane, Tim (2001). The significance of emergence. In: Carl Gillett and Barry Loewer (eds.) Physicalism and Its Discontents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
◈ Craver, Carl F. and William Bechtel (in press). Top-down Causation Without Top-down Causes. Biology and Philosophy.
Received: 22 December 2005 Accepted: 10 March 2006 Published online: 27 May 2006
◈ Crick, Francis (Sep. 1979). Thinking about the brain. Scientific American 241(3): 219-232.
▣ Crisp, Thomas M. and Ted A. Warfield (June 2001). Kim’s Master Argument: A critical study of Jaegwon Kim's Mind in a Physical World. Nous 35(2): 304–316.
◈ Crutchfield, James P. (1994). Is anything ever new?: Considering emergence. In G. Cowan, D. Pines, D. Melzner (eds.) Integrative Themes. Santa Fe Institute Studies in the Sciences of Complexity XIX. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. [SFI 94-03-011]
◈ Crutchfield, James P., J. Doyne Farmer, Norman H. Packard (Dec. 1986). Chaos. Scientific American 255(6): 38-49.
◈ Cunningham, Bryon (Sep. 2001). The Reemergence of 'emergence' (the theory that a whole is greater than its parts). Philosophy of Science 68(3): S62-S75.
◈ Damasio, Antonio R. (Oct. 25, 2001). Fundamental feelings: Emotion. Nature 413: 781.
◈ Damasio, Antonio R. (May 15, 2003). Mental self: The person within. Nature 423: 227.
◇ Dardis, Anthony (2002). A "no causal rivalry" Solution to the Problem of Mental Causation. Acta Analytica 17(28):
Abstract: Stephen Yablo has recently argued for a novel solution to the mental causation problem: the mental is related to the physical as determinables are related to determinates; determinables are not causal rivals with their determinates; so the mental and the physical are not causal rivals. Despite its attractions the suggestion seems hard to accept. In this paper I develop the idea that mental properties and physical properties are not causal rivals. Start with property dualism, supervenience, multiple realizability, and the claim that no more than one supervenience base for a mental property can be had by a single instance of the mental property. Then a probabilistic account of causation will be unable to certify either mental properties or physical properties as causal factors for effect types. I suggest that this shows that we should not count mental properties as causal rivals with physical properties.
Keywords: Mental causation, Probabilistic causation, Supervenience, Mind/Body Problem, Non-reductive physicalism
◈ Davies, Paul C.W. (2004a). Does quantum mechanics play a non-trivial role in life? BioSystems 78: 69-79.
◈ Davies, Paul C.W. (2004b). Emergent biological principles and the computational properties of the universe: Explaining it or explaining it away. Complexity 10(2): 11-15.
◈ Davies, Paul C.W. (2006). The Physics of Downward Causation. In Philip Clayton and Paul Davies (eds.) The Re-Emergence of Emergence: The Emergentist Hypothesis from Science to Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
▣ Deacon, Terrence W. (July 1997). The Symbolic Species: The Co-Evolution of Language and the Brain. W.W. Norton & Company.
◈ Deacon, Terrence W. (July 2003). Multilevel Selection in a Complex Adaptive System: The Problem of Language Origins. In Bruce H. Weber and David J. Depew eds. Evolution and Learning: The Baldwin Effect Reconsidered. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
◈ Deacon, Terrence W. (July 2003). The Hierarchic Logic of Emergence: Untangling the Interdependence of Evolution and Self-Organization. In Bruce H. Weber and David J. Depew eds. Evolution and Learning: The Baldwin Effect Reconsidered. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
◈ Deacon, Terrence W. (June 2006). Emergence: The Hole at the Wheel's Hub. In Philip Clayton and Paul Davies eds. The Re-Emergence of Emergence: The Emergentist Hypothesis from Science to Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
▣ Deacon, Terrence W. (Spring, 2006). Reciprocal linkage between self-organizing processes is sufficient for self-reproduction and evolvability. Biological Theory 1(2): 136-149.
Posted Online October 3, 2006. (doi:10.1162/biot.2006.1.2.136)
Terrence W. Deacon : Department of Anthropology and HelenWills Neuroscience Institute, University of California, Berkeley, CA, USA
A simple molecular system ("autocell") is described consisting of the reciprocal linkage between an autocatalytic cycle and a self-assembling encapsulation process where the molecular constituents for the capsule are products of the autocatalysis. In a molecular environment sufficiently rich in the substrates, capsule growth will also occur with high predictability. Growth to closure will be most probable in the vicinity of the most prolific autocatalysis and will thus tend to spontaneously enclose supportive catalysts within the capsule interior. If subsequently disrupted in the presence of new substrates, the released components will initiate production of additional catalytic and capsule components that will spontaneously re-assemble into one or more autocell replicas, thereby reconstituting and sometimes reproducing the original. In a diverse molecular environment, cycles of disruption and enclosure will cause auto- cells to incidentally encapsulate other molecules as well as reactive substrates. To the extent that any captured molecule can be incorporated into the autocatalytic process by virtue of structural degeneracy of the catalytic binding sites, the altered autocell will incorporate the new type of component into subsequent replications. Such altered autocells will be progenitors of "lineages" with variant characteristics that will differentially propagate with respect to the availability of commonly required substrates. Autocells are susceptible to a limited form of evolution, capable of leading to more efficient, more environmentally fitted, and more complex forms. This provides a simple demonstration of the plausibility of open- ended reproduction and evolvability without self-replicating template molecules (e.g., nucleic acids) or maintenance of persistent nonequilibrium chemistry. This model identifies an intermediate domain between prebiotic and biotic systems and bridges the gap from nonequilibrium thermodynamics to life.
◈ Deacon, Terrence W. (forthcoming). Homunculus: Evolution, Information, and the Emergence of Consciousness. W.W. Norton.
◈ Deacon, Terrence W. (forthcoming). Golem: Making Things Think.
◈ Deacon, Terrence W. (forthcoming). Homo Sapiens: Evolutionary Biology and the Human Sciences. Thompson/Wadsworth.
◈ Deguet, Joris, Yves Demazeau (2005). Elements about the Emergence Issue: A survey of emergence definitions.
Abstract: Emergence, a concept that first appeared in philosophy, has been widely explored in the domain of complex systems and is sometimes considered to be the key ingredient that makes “complex systems” “complex”. Our goal in this paper is to give a broad survey of emergence definitions, to extract a shared definition structure and to discuss some of the remaining issues. We do not know of any comparable surveys about the emergence concept. For this presentation, we start from a broadly applicable approach and finish with more specific propositions. We first present five selected works with a short analysis of each. We then propose a merged analysis in which we isolate a common structure through all definitions but also what we think needs further research. Finally, we briefly describe some perspectives about the emergence engine idea also referred to as emergent engineering.
Keywords: survey, emergence, complexity, levels definition
https://lig.imag.fr/MAGMA/publications/papers/Deguet-Demazeau-Magnin-05.pdf
◆ Delacour, Jean (Apr. 1, 1997). Object Perception and Recognition: A Model for the Scientific Study of Consciousness. Theory & Psychology 7(2): 257-262.
The main obstacles to the scientific study of consciousness are its subjectivity and its complexity. Object perception and recognition (OPR) can be a useful model in such a study because there is a remarkable agreement between the subjective and objective aspects of OPR; in addition, while OPR is somewhat simpler than other forms of cognition, it adequately represents one characteristic feature of consciousness: intentionality. It thus allows convergent studies of experimental psychology, artificial intelligence and biology, in both humans and animals. Recent advances in the neurophysiology of visual OPR in subhuman primates and its brain imaging in humans provide a vital thread to the neural basis of consciousness, especially of its integrative, unifying character.
Key Words: binding • consciousness • intentionality • object perception • world
◈ De Muijnck, Wim (2003/2006). Dependencies, Connections, and Other Relations: A Theory of Mental Causation. Kluwer Academic Publishers/Springer.
◈ De Sousa, Ronald (1994). Individualism and Local Control in Complex Systems. Canadian Journal of Philosophy suppl. vol. 20:165-185.
◈ De Wolf, Tom and Tom Holvoet (2005). Emergence Versus Self-Organisation: Different Concepts but Promising When Combined. Engineering Self Organising Systems: Methodologies and Applications (Brueckner, S. and Di Marzo Serugendo, G. and Karageorgos, A. and Nagpal, R., eds.), Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2005, Volume 3464, May 2005, pages 1-15.
Abstract: A clear terminology is essential in every research discipline. In the context of ESOA, a lot of confusion exists about the meaning of the terms emergence and self-organisation. One of the sources of the confusion comes from the fact that a combination of both phenomena often occurs in dynamical systems. In this paper a historic overview of the use of each concept as well as a working definition, that is compatible with the historic and current meaning of the concepts, is given. Each definition is explained by supporting it with import!ant characteristics found in the literature. We show that emergence and self-organisation each emphasise different properties of a system. Both phenomena can exist in isolation. The paper also outlines some examples of such systems and considers the combination of emergence and self-organisation as a promising approach in complex multi-agent systems.
http://www.cs.kuleuven.be/~tomdw/publications/pdfs/2005esoa04lncs.pdf
http://www.cs.kuleuven.be/~tomdw/
◆ Eccles, John C. (1982). How the self acts on the brain. Psychoneuroendocrinology 7(4): 271-283.
◆ Eccles, John C. (May 22, 1986). Do mental events cause neural events analogously to the probability fields of quantum mechanics? Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences 227(1249): 411-428.
If non-material mental events, such as the intention to carry out an action, are to have an effective action on neural events in the brain, it has to be at the most subtle and plastic level of these events. In the first stage of our enquiry an introduction to conventional synaptic theory leads on to an account of the manner of operation of the ultimate synaptic units. These units are the synaptic boutons that, when excited by an all-or-nothing nerve impulse, deliver the total contents of a single synaptic vesicle, not regularly, but probabilistically. This quantal emission of the synaptic transmitter molecules (about 5000-10 000) is the elementary unit of the transmission process from one neuron to another. In the second stage this refined physiological analysis leads on to an account of the ultrastructure of the synapse, which gives clues as to the manner of its unitary probabilistic operation. The essential feature is that the effective structure of each bouton is a paracrystalline presynaptic vesicular grid with about 50 vesicles, which acts probabilistically in vesicular (quantal) release. In the third stage it is considered how a non-material mental event, such as an intention to move, could influence the subtle probabilistic operations of synaptic boutons. On the biological side, attention is focused on the paracrystalline presynaptic vesicular grids as the targets for non-material mental events. On the physical side, attention is focused on the probabilistic fields of quantum mechanics which carry neither mass nor energy, but which nevertheless can exert effective action at microsites. The new light on the mind-brain problem came from the hypothesis that the non-material mental events, the 'World 2' of Popper, relate to the neural events of the brain (the 'World 1' of matter and energy) by actions in conformity with quantum theory. This hypothesis that mental events act on probabilistic synaptic events in a manner analogous to the probability fields of quantum mechanics seems to open up an immense field of scientific investigation both in quantum physics and in neuroscience.
◈ Eccles, John C. (Aug. 1992). Evolution of consciousness. PNAS 89: 7320-7324.
The hypothesis of the origin of consciousness is built upon the unique properties of the mammalian neocortex. The apical dendrites of the pyramidal cells bundle together as they ascend to lamina I to form neural receptor units of 100 apical dendrites plus branches receiving hundreds of thousands of excitatory synapses, the collective assemblage being called a dendron. It is proposed that the whole world of consciousness, the mental world, is microgranular, with mental units called psychons, and that in mind-brain interaction one psychon is linked to one dendron through quantum physics. The hypothesis is that in mammalian evolution dendrons evolved for more effective integration of the increased complexity of sensory inputs. These evolved dendrons had the capacity for interacting with psychons that came to exist, so forming the mental world and giving the mammal conscious experiences. In Darwinian evolution, consciousness would have occurred initially some 200 million years ago in relation to the primitive cerebral cortices of evolving mammals. It would give global experiences of a surrounding world for guiding behavior beyond what is given by the unconscious operation of sensory cortical areas per se. So conscious experiences would give mammals evolutionary advantage over the reptiles, which lack a neocortex giving consciousness. The Wulst of the avian brain needs further investigation to discover how it could give birds the consciousness that they seem to have.
◇ Ecological Modelling Volume 186, Issue 4, Pages 375-510 (10 September 2005).
Special Issue on: Emergent Properties in Individual-based Models Case Studies from the Bornhöved Project (Northern Germany)
Edited by Broder Breckling
Emergent properties in individual-based ecological models—introducing case studies in an ecosystem research context
Pages 376-388
Broder Breckling, Felix Müller, Hauke Reuter, Franz Hölker and Otto Fränzle
Dispersal of carabid beetles—emergence of distribution patterns
Pages 389-405
Fred Jopp and Hauke Reuter
A spatiotemporal individual-based fish model to investigate emergent properties at the organismal and the population level
Pages 406-426
Franz Hölker and Broder Breckling
Community processes as emergent properties: Modelling multilevel interaction in small mammals communities
Pages 427-446
Hauke Reuter
From single fine roots to a black alder forest ecosystem: How system behaviour emerges from single component activities
Pages 447-469
Ulrike Middelhoff and Broder Breckling
Emergent properties modelled with the functional structural tree growth model ALMIS: Computer experiments on resource gain and use
Pages 470-488
Christiane Eschenbach
The concepts of emergent and collective properties in individual-based models—Summary and outlook of the Bornhöved case studies
Pages 489-501
Hauke Reuter, Franz Hölker, Ulrike Middelhoff, Fred Jopp, Christiane Eschenbach and Broder Breckling
◈ Edelman, Gerald M. (Apr. 29, 2003). Naturalizing consciousness: A theoretical framework. PNAS 100(9): 5520-5524.
▣ Edelmann, J.B. and M.J. Denton (in press. Dec. 13, 2006). The uniqueness of biological self-organization: challenging the Darwinian paradigm. Biology and Philosophy.
Received: 17 November 2005 Accepted: 26 October 2006 Published online: 13 December 2006
Abstract: Here we discuss the challenge posed by self-organization to the Darwinian conception of evolution. As we point out, natural selection can only be the major creative agency in evolution if all or most of the adaptive complexity manifest in living organisms is built up over many generations by the cumulative selection of naturally occurring small, random mutations or variants, i.e., additive, incremental steps over an extended period of time. Biological self-organization—witnessed classically in the folding of a protein, or in the formation of the cell membrane—is a fundamentally different means of generating complexity. We agree that self-organizing systems may be fine-tuned by selection and that self-organization may be therefore considered a complementary mechanism to natural selection as a causal agency in the evolution of life. But we argue that if self-organization proves to be a common mechanism for the generation of adaptive order from the molecular to the organismic level, then this will greatly undermine the Darwinian claim that natural selection is the major creative agency in evolution. We also point out that although complex self-organizing systems are easy to create in the electronic realm of cellular automata, to date translating in silico simulations into real material structures that self-organize into complex forms from local interactions between their constituents has not proved easy. This suggests that self-organizing systems analogous to those utilized by biological systems are at least rare and may indeed represent, as pre-Darwinists believed, a unique ascending hierarchy of natural forms. Such a unique adaptive hierarchy would pose another major challenge to the current Darwinian view of evolution, as it would mean the basic forms of life are necessary features of the order of nature and that the major pathways of evolution are determined by physical law, or more specifically by the self-organizing properties of biomatter, rather than natural selection.
Keywords: Self-organization - Cumulative selection - Unique hierarchy of natural forms - Contingency - Necessity - Robustness - Pre-Darwinian
◈ Ehresmann, Andrée C., Jean-Paul Vanbremeersch, Laura McNamara and Mary Meyer (May 2007). Memory Evolutive Systems; Hierarchy, Emergence, Cognition. Elsevier.
Part A: Hierarchy. Emergence
Chapter 1: Net of Interactions and Categories
Chapter 2: The Binding Problem
Chapter 3: Hierarchy and Reductionism
Chapter 4: Complexifications and Emergence
Part B: Memory Evolutive Systems
Chapter 5: Evolutionary Systems
Chapter 6: Internal Organization and MES
Chapter 7: Robustness and Plasiticity
Chapter 8: Memory and Learning
Part C: Application to Cognition and Consciousness
Chapter 9: Cognitive Systems and MES of CAT-Neurons
Chapter10: Semantics, Archetypal Core and Consciousness
▣ Elder, Crawford L. (Jan. 2001). Mental Causation Versus physical Causation: No Contest. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62(1): 111–127.
◈ El-Hani, Charbel Niño (2002). On the Reality of Emergents. Principia, Special Issue on Emergence and Downward Causation (El-Hani, C.N. Ed.) 6: 51-87.
◈ El-Hani, Charbel Niño (presented Jan. 29th, 2004). Towards a coherent account of emergence and downward causation in the natural sciences.
Available online http://www.helsinki.fi/filosofia/tutkijaseminaari/El%20Hani.pdf
◈ El-Hani, Charbel Niño, Claus Emmeche (2000). On some theoretical grounds for an organism-centered biology: Property emergence, supervenience, and downward causation. Theory in Biosciences 119: 234-275.
◈ El-Hani, Charbel Niño, Sami Pihlström (2002a). Emergence Theories and Pragmatic Realism. Essays in Philosophy 3(2): 1-40.
Available online http://www.humboldt.edu/~essays/pihlstrom.html
◈ El-Hani, Charbel Niño, Sami Pihlström (2002b). A Pragmatic Realist View of Emergence. Manuscrito XXV (Sp. number): 105-154.
◈ El-Hani, Charbel Niño, João Queiroz (2005). Downward determination. Abstracta 1(2): 162-192.
Available online http://www.dca.fee.unicamp.br/projects/artcog/files/ElHani_Queiroz_Abstracta_paper.pdf
◇ Ellerman, David (Mar. 2007). Adjoints and emergence: applications of a new theory of adjoint functors. Axiomathes 17(1): 19-39.
Received: 16 January 2007 Accepted: 24 January 2007 Published online: 8 March 2007
Abstract: Since its formal definition over sixty years ago, category theory has been increasingly recognized as having a foundational role in mathematics. It provides the conceptual lens to isolate and characterize the structures with importance and universality in mathematics. The notion of an adjunction (a pair of adjoint functors) has moved to center-stage as the principal lens. The central feature of an adjunction is what might be called “determination through universals” based on universal mapping properties. A recently developed “heteromorphic” theory about adjoints suggests a conceptual structure, albeit abstract and atemporal, for how new relatively autonomous behavior can emerge within a system obeying certain laws. The focus here is on applications in the life sciences (e.g., selectionist mechanisms) and human sciences (e.g., the generative grammar view of language).
Keywords: Adjoint functors - Category theory - Universal mapping properties - Heteromorphisms - Emergence - Evolution - Selectionist mechanisms - Immune system - Neural selectionism - Generative grammar
◈ Ellis, George F.R. (Jun. 9, 2005). Physics, complexity and causality. Nature 435: 743.
◈ Ellis, George F.R. (Jun 14, 2005). Physics and the real world.
Available online http://www.metanexus.net/conference2005/pdf/ellis.pdf
◈ Ellis, George F.R. (2007). Science, complexity, and the nature of existence. Published in: Nancey Murphy, William R. Stoeger, SJ (eds.) Evolution and Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◈ Emmeche, Claus (1994). The Garden in the Machine: The Emerging Science of Artificial Life. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
◈ Emmeche, Claus (1997). Defining Life, Explaining Emergence. (Published in two parts as: Emmeche, Claus (1997). Autopoietic Systems, Replicators, and the Search for a Meaningful Biologic Definition of Life. Ultimate Reality and Meaning 20: 244-264; Emmeche, Claus (1998). Defining Life as a Semiotic Phenomenon. Cybernetics & Human Knowing 5: 3-17.)
On-line paper http://www.nbi.dk/~emmeche/
◈ Emmeche, Claus, Simo Køppe and Frederik Stjernfelt (1997). Explaining Emergence: Towards an Ontology of Levels. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 28: 83-119.
◈ Emmeche, Claus, Simo Køppe and Frederik Stjernfelt (2000). Levels, emergence, and three versions of downward causation. Published pp. 13-34 in: Peter Bøgh Andersen, Claus Emmeche, Niels Ole Finnemann and Peder Voetmann Christiansen (eds.) (2000). Downward Causation: Minds, bodies and matter. Aarhus: Aarhus University Press.
▣ Engel, Gregory S., Tessa R. Calhoun, Elizabeth L. Read, Tae-Kyu Ahn, Tomá Man al, Yuan-Chung Cheng, Robert E. Blankenship & Graham R. Fleming (Apr. 12, 2007). Evidence for wavelike energy transfer through quantum coherence in photosynthetic systems. Nature 446(7137): 782-786.
Gregory S. Engel1,2, Tessa R. Calhoun1,2, Elizabeth L. Read1,2, Tae-Kyu Ahn1,2, Tomá Man al1,2,5, Yuan-Chung Cheng1,2, Robert E. Blankenship3,4 & Graham R. Fleming1,2
Received 13 October 2006; Accepted 14 February 2007
Photosynthetic complexes are exquisitely tuned to capture solar light efficiently, and then transmit the excitation energy to reaction centres, where long term energy storage is initiated. The energy transfer mechanism is often described by semiclassical models that invoke 'hopping' of excited-state populations along discrete energy levels1, 2. Two-dimensional Fourier transform electronic spectroscopy3, 4, 5 has mapped6 these energy levels and their coupling in the Fenna–Matthews–Olson (FMO) bacteriochlorophyll complex, which is found in green sulphur bacteria and acts as an energy 'wire' connecting a large peripheral light-harvesting antenna, the chlorosome, to the reaction centre7, 8, 9. The spectroscopic data clearly document the dependence of the dominant energy transport pathways on the spatial properties of the excited-state wavefunctions of the whole bacteriochlorophyll complex6, 10. But the intricate dynamics of quantum coherence, which has no classical analogue, was largely neglected in the analyses—even though electronic energy transfer involving oscillatory populations of donors and acceptors was first discussed more than 70 years ago11, and electronic quantum beats arising from quantum coherence in photosynthetic complexes have been predicted12, 13 and indirectly observed14. Here we extend previous two-dimensional electronic spectroscopy investigations of the FMO bacteriochlorophyll complex, and obtain direct evidence for remarkably long-lived electronic quantum coherence playing an important part in energy transfer processes within this system. The quantum coherence manifests itself in characteristic, directly observable quantum beating signals among the excitons within the Chlorobium tepidum FMO complex at 77 K. This wavelike characteristic of the energy transfer within the photosynthetic complex can explain its extreme efficiency, in that it allows the complexes to sample vast areas of phase space to find the most efficient path.
☞ see Scientific American's Science News by David Biello: When It Comes to Photosynthesis, Plants Perform Quantum Computation.
http://www.sciam.com/article.cfm?articleID=ED1D1446-E7F2-99DF-3CBF8B2F66C0C5D4&sc=I100322
◇ Esfeld, Michael and Christian Sachse (Mar. 2007). Theory Reduction by Means of Functional Sub-types. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 21(1): 1-17. (DOI: 10.1080/02698590701305735)
Abstract: The paper sets out a new strategy for theory reduction by means of functional sub-types. This strategy is intended to get around the multiple realization objection. We use Kim's argument for token identity (ontological reductionism) based on the causal exclusion problem as starting point. We then extend ontological reductionism to epistemological reductionism (theory reduction). We show how one can distinguish within any functional type between functional sub-types. Each of these sub-types is coextensive with one type of realizer. By this means, a conservative theory reduction is in principle possible, despite multiple realization. We link this account with Nagelian reduction, as well as with Kim's functional reduction.
◈ Ezquerro, Jesús and Fernando Martínez Manrique (Apr. 2004). Intertheory Relations in Cognitive Science: Privileged Levels and Reductive Strategies. Crítica, Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía, Vol. 36, No. 106, April 2004, pp. 55-103.
http://critica.filosoficas.unam.mx/pdf/C106/C106_ezquerromartinez.pdf
Abstract: Research in cognitive science has often assumed the existence of a privileged level that unifies theoretical explanations arising from different disciplines. Philosophical accounts differ about the locus of those intertheory relations. In this paper, four different views are analyzed: classical, connectionist, pragmatist, and reductionist, as exemplified in the works of von Eckardt, Horgan and Tienson, Hardcastle, and Bickle, respectively. Their divergences are characterized in terms of the possibility of such a privileged level. The classical view favors a privileged computational level. The connectionist revision tries to draw biological intuitions into computational models to provide a link between neuronsand computations. The pragmatist approach rejects the idea of a privileged level and offers a more eclectic view of cognitive theory building. The reductionist account pursues theoretical unification by means of the reduction of higher level theories to basic level (biological) ones.
Keywords: cognitive science, computationalism, connectionism,reduction
http://critica.filosoficas.unam.mx/106/sum106_esquerromartinez_in.html
■ Feltz, Bernard, Marc Crommelinck, Philippe Goujon (eds.) (2006). Self-organization and Emergence in Life Sciences. Springer.
About this book
Self-organization constitutes one of the most important theoretical debates in contemporary life sciences. The present book explores the relevance of the concept of self-organization and its impact on such scientific fields as: immunology, neurosciences, ecology and theories of evolution.
Historical aspects of the issue are also broached. Intuitions relative to self-organization can be found in the works of such key western philosophical figures as Aristotle, Leibniz and Kant. Interacting with more recent authors and cybernetics, self-organization represents a notion in keeping with the modern world's discovery of radical complexity.
The themes of teleology and emergence are analyzed by philosophers of sciences with regards to the issues of modelization and scientific explanation.
The implications of self-organization for life sciences are here approached from an interdisciplinary angle, revealing the notion as already rewarding and full of promise for the future.
Table of contents
List of Contributors. Introduction; Bernard Feltz, Marc Crommelinck and Philippe Goujon.
I. Scientific Approach.
A. Self-Organization and Biology: General Standpoints.
The Complex Adaptative Systems Approach to Biology; Gérard Weisbuch. Emergence and Reductionism: from the Game of Life to Science of Life; Vincent Bauchau. Formalizing Emergence: the Natural After-Life of Artificial Life; Hugues Bersini.
B. Self-Organization and Biology: Thematic Standpoints.
Analysis and Synthesis of Regulator Networks in Terms of Feedback Circuits; René Thomas. Properties Emerging from Sensorimotor Interfaces. Interaction Between Experimentation and Modeling in Neurosciences; Philippe Lefèvre, Cheng Tu, Marcus Missal and Marc Crommelinck. Neuronal Synchrony and Cognitive Functions; Francisco Varela. About Biology and Subjectivity in Psychiatry; Philippe Meire. Self-Organization and Meaning in Immunology; Henri Atlan and Irun Cohen.
II. Historic Approach.
A. Early Philosophical Conceptualizations.
Kant and the Intuitions of Self-Organization; Gertrudis Van de Vijver. On a "Mathematical Neo-Aristotelism" in Leibniz; Laurence Bouquiaux. "Essential Force" and "Formative Force": Models for Epigenesis in the 18th Century; François Duchesneau. From Logic to Self-Organization. Learning about Complexity; Philippe Goujon. The Concept of Emergence in the XIXth Century: from Natural Theology to Biology; Paul Mengal.
B. Contemporary Origins.
Artificial Life and the Sciences of Complexity: History and Future; Jean-Claude Heudin. Self-Organization in Second-Order Cybernetics: Deconstruction or Reconstruction of Complexity; Pierre Livet.
III. Epistemological and Conceptual Approaches.
A. Teleology and Intentionality.
Teleology in Self-Organizing Systems; Robert Brandon. Phenomenology and Self-Organization; Marc Maesschalck and Valérie Kokoszka.
B. Explanation.
A Role for Mathematical Models in Formalizing Self-Organizing Systems; Paul Thompson. Explanation and Causality in Self-Organizing Systems; Robert C. Richardson. Self-Organization, Selection and Emergence in the Theories of Evolution; Bernard Feltz.
■ Finney, John L. (Aug. 29, 2004). Water? What's so special about it? Philosophical Transactions of The Royal Society B (Biological Sciences) 359(1448): 1145-1165. (doi:10.1098/rstb.2004.1495)
Abstract: What is so special about water? Why does it have the properties it has, and how might these reasons be relevant to its apparent biological importance? By exploring the structure and dynamics of water, from the isolated molecule and its interactions, through its many crystalline phases and to its so-called anomalous liquid phase, some of its apparently unusual behaviour is rationalized. The way in which it interacts with some relatively simple interfaces is also discussed. As a result of this exploration, a checklist of possible molecular-level reasons for its biological importance is devised.
Keywords: Water Molecule, Water-Water Interactions, Ices, Liquid Water, Anomalous Properties
▣ Fodor, Jerry (1974). Special Sciences, or The Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis. Reprinted in Jerry Fodor (1981). Representations. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
■ Francescotti, Robert Michael (July 2007). Emergence. Erkenntnis 67(1): 47-63. (DOI:10.1007/s10670-007-9047-0)
(1) | Philosophy, San Diego State University, 5500 Campanile Drive, San Diego, CA 92182, USA |
Received: 17 January 2006 Accepted: 27 March 2007 Published online: 3 May 2007
Keywords: Downward causation - Emergent properties - Novelty - Parts - Predictability - Relationality - Supervenience - Wholes
◈ Frecska, E. and L.E. Luna (Oct. 2006). Neuro-ontological interpretation of spiritual experiences. Neuropsychopharmacologia Hungarica (official journal of the Hungarian Association of Psychopharmacology) 8(3): 143-153.
◈ Freeman, Walter J. & Giuseppe Vitiello (2006). Nonlinear brain dynamics as macroscopic many-body field dynamics. Physics of Life Reviews 3: 93-118.
◆ French, Christopher C. (2005). Near-death experiences in cardiac arrest survivors. Progress in Brain Research 150: 351-367.
Available online 25 September 2005.
Abstract: Near-death experiences (NDEs) have become the focus of much interest in the last 30 years or so. Such experiences can occur both when individuals are objectively near to death and also when they simply believe themselves to be. The experience typically involves a number of different components including a feeling of peace and well-being, out-of-body experiences (OBEs), entering a region of darkness, seeing a brilliant light, and entering another realm. NDEs are known to have long-lasting transformational effects upon those who experience them. An overview is presented of the various theoretical approaches that have been adopted in attempts to account for the NDE. Spiritual theories assume that consciousness can become detached from the neural substrate of the brain and that the NDE may provide a glimpse of an afterlife. Psychological theories include the proposal that the NDE is a dissociative defense mechanism that occurs in times of extreme danger or, less plausibly, that the NDE reflects memories of being born. Finally, a wide range of organic theories of the NDE has been put forward including those based upon cerebral hypoxia, anoxia, and hypercarbia; endorphins and other neurotransmitters; and abnormal activity in the temporal lobes. Finally, the results of studies of NDEs in cardiac arrest survivors are reviewed and the implications of these results for our understanding of mind–brain relationships are discussed.
◈ Gabora, Liane (1999). Microtubules, anesthetics, and quantum consciousness: an interview with Stuart Hameroff. Foundations of Science 4: 205-223.
◈ Gärdenfors, Peter (2005). The Emergence of Thought. In David Martel Johnson and Christina E. Erneling eds. The Mind as a Scientific Object: Between Brain and Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◆ Garnett, A. Campbell (Aug. 27, 1942). Scientific Method and the Concept of Emergence. The Journal of Philosophy 39(18): 477-486.
In their theories of the relation of the mental and the physical most thinkers today seek to avoid both the Scylla of dualism and the Charybdis of reductionism. There then remain two possibilities, (a) that mental processes have emerged from a matrix of events that once was entirely non-mental, (b) that life and mind as we know them have developed within a world matrix that has always contained mental processes in some form. Among thinkers who have insisted on scientific method in philosophy the former hypothesis is widely accepted. It is the aim of this paper to show that such a theory of emergence is not consistent with the strict demands of scientific method.
◈ Gell-Mann, Murray (Apr. 2001). Consciousness, Reduction, and Emergence: Some Remarks. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 929(1): 41-49.
▣ Georgiev, Danko Dimchev (Mar. 2007). Falsifications of Hameroff-Penrose Orch OR Model of Consciousness and Novel Avenues for Development of Quantum Mind Theory. NeuroQuantology 5(1): 145-174. www.neuroquantology.com
Abstract: In this paper we try to make a clear distinction between quantum mysticism and quantum mind theory. Quackery always accompanies science especially in controversial and still under development areas and since the quantum mind theory is a science youngster it must clearly demarcate itself from the great stuff of pseudo-science currently patronized by the term “quantum mind”. Quantum theory has attracted a big deal of attention and opened new avenues for building up a physical theory of mind because its principles and experimental foundations are as strange as the phenomenon of consciousness itself. Yet, the unwarranted recourse to paranormal phenomena as supporting the quantum mind theory plus the extremely bad biological mismodeling of brain physiology lead to great scepticism about the viability of the approach. We give as an example the Hameroff-Penrose Orch OR model with a list of twenty four problems not being repaired for a whole decade after the birth of the model in 1996. In the exposition we have tried not only to pesent critique of the spotted flaws, but to provide novel possibilities towards creation of neuroscientific quantum model of mind that incorporates all the available data from the basic disciplines (biochemistry, cell physiology, etc.) up to the clinical observations (neurology, neurosurgery, molecular psychiatry, etc.). Thus in a concise fashion we outline what can be done scientifically to improve the Q-mind theory and start a research programme (in Lakatos sense) that is independent on the particular flaws in some of the existing Q-mind models.
Key Words: Hameroff and Penrose Theory, OrchOR, objective reduction, quantum mind, microtubules, neuron, consciousness
◈ Gibb, Sophie (Sep. 2006). Why Davidson is not a Property Epiphenomenalist. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 14(3): 407 - 422.
Abstract: Despite the fact that Davidson's theory of the causal relata is crucial to his response to the problem of mental causation - that of anomalous monism - it is commonly overlooked within discussions of his position. Anomalous monism is accused of entailing property epiphenomenalism, but given Davidson's understanding of the causal relata, such accusations are wholly misguided. There are, I suggest, two different forms of property epiphenomenalism. The first understands the term 'property' in an ontological sense, the second in a linguistic sense. Anomalous monism cannot plausibly be accused of either. The first cannot legitimately be applied to anomalous monism as it is incompatible with Davidson's ontology. And accusations of predicate epiphenomenalism, although consistent with Davidson's ontology, are ungrounded regarding Davidson's anomalous monism. Philosophers of mind have mislocated the problem with Davidson's anomalous monism, which in fact lies with the implausible theory of the causal relata upon which it rests.
Keywords: Davidson; anomalous monism; epiphenomenalism; property; mental causation
▣ Gibbons, John (Jan. 2006). Mental Causation without Downward Causation. Philosophical Review 115(1): 79-103.
http://philreview.dukejournals.org/cgi/reprint/115/1/79.pdf
■ Gibson, James Jerome (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Houghton Mifflin.
◈ Gillett, Carl (2001). Does the Argument from Realization Generalize? Responses to Kim. Southern Journal of Philosophy 39: 79-98.
◈ Gillett, Carl (2002a) The Dimensions of Realization: A Critique of the Standard View, Analysis 62: 316-23.
◈ Gillett, Carl (2002b) The Varieties of Emergence: Their Purposes, Obligations and Importance. Grazer Philosophische Studien 65: 89-115.
Abstract: I outline reasons for the recent popularity, and lingering suspicion, about ‘emergence’ by examining three distinct concepts of property emergence, their purposes and associated obligations. In Part 1, I argue ‘Strong’ emergence is the grail for many emergentists (and physicalists), since it frames what is needed to block the ‘Argument from Realization’ (AR) which moves from the truth of physicalism to the inefficacy of special science properties. I then distinguish ‘Weak’ and ‘Ontological’ emergence, in Part 2, arguing each is a way one may fail to establish the possibility of Strong emergence. But I also show Weak emergence can help the full-blown reductionists and Ontological emergence helps those opposed to physicalism. Lastly, in Part 3, I argue that the Completeness of Physics (CP) is incompatible with Strong emergence and that rejecting CP provides hope for the possibility of Strong emergence in a physical world. My final conclusion is that concepts of emergence, when properly understood, have important contributions to make to philosophical debate.
◈ Gillett, Carl (2003a). Strong Emergence as a Defense of Non-Reductive Physicalism: A Physicalist Metaphysics for ‘Downward’ Determination, Principia 6: 83-114.
Abstract: Jaegwon Kim, and others, have recently posed a powerful challenge to both emergentism and non-reductive physicalism by providing arguments that these positions are committed to an untenable combination of both ‘upward’ and ‘downward’ determination. In Part 1, I illuminate how the nature of the realization relation underlies such skeptical arguments. However, in Part 2, I suggest that such conclusions involve a confusion between the implications of physicalism and those of a related thesis in the ‘Completeness of Physics’ (CoP). I show that the truth of CoP poses a very serious obstacle to realized properties being efficacious in a physicalist universe and suggest that abandoning CoP offers hope for defending non-reductive physicalism. I then formulate a schema for a physicalist metaphysics, in Part 3, which rejects CoP. This scenario is one where microphysical properties have a few conditional powers that they contribute to individuals when they realize certain properties. In such a situation, I argue, though physicalism holds true there is still plausibly both ‘upward’ and ‘downward’ determination, where the latter is crucially an under-appreciated form of determination I term ‘non-causal’. Ultimately, I conclude that this metaphysical schema offers a coherent account of Strongly emergent properties that preserves the truth of NRP, albeit in a form that is purged of any commitment to CoP. Finally, in Part 4, I carefully explore which of Kim’s assumptions and arguments this metaphysics undermines.
◈ Gillett, Carl (2003b) Non-Reductive Realization and Non-Reductive Identity: What Physicalism does not Entail. Published in: Sven Walter and Heinz-Dieter Heckmann (eds.) Physicalism and Mental Causation. London, Mentis.
Abstract: Reductionism has been rejuvenated by a metaphysical turn engineered by Jaegwon Kim using realization relations to effect metaphysical reductions. I outline Kim’s new ‘Functionalization’ model of reduction, in Part 1, focussing upon the key argument underlying its reductionist credentials, what I term the ‘Argument from Realization’ (AR). However, in Part 2, I illuminate a type of a realized property covered by the Functionalization model, but which I will argue is irreducible, contrary to Kim’s claims and AR. Furthermore, in Part 3, I show that this variety of realized property also illuminates that type identity does not necessarily lead to metaphysical reductionism either. In Part 4, I will consider an important objection to my scenario for irreducible realized properties, but I will suggest that it fails because it conflates non-causal and causal determination. My conclusion, in Part 5, will be that, contra Kim, universal realization does allow for a truly non-reductive or “Patchwork” physicalism and does not entail the truth of metaphysical reductionism.
◈ Gillett, Carl (2003c). The Metaphysics of Realization, Multiple Realizability and the Special Sciences. Journal of Philosophy. 591-603.
Abstract: The ‘received’ view of multiple realizability (henceforth ‘MR’) and the special sciences was originally laid out in the seventies in a famous paper by Jerry Fodor. Recently, a range of criticisms have been offered of this position and the most significant is provided by Lawrence A. Shapiro’s (2000) in which he defends a prima facie plausible criterion for MR which he then uses to critique the received view of both MR and special sciences themselves. However, like other critics, Shapiro does not offer a precise account of realization and it appears plausible that such an account is a necessary step in any precise understanding of multiple realization. My main goal will be to argue this oversight is indeed damaging and that work on the metaphysics of realization has an important role to play in the philosophy of psychology. For I will show that differences over the metaphysics of realization are inextricably bound-up with broader disputes over the nature, and extent, of MR. As a result, I shall argue that although we should endorse Shapiro’s important criterion for MR, his criticisms of the received view, and those of another prominent critique, beg the question against his opponents.
◈ Gillett, Carl (2006). The Hidden Battles over Emergence. Published in: Philip Clayton, Zachary Simpson (eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Religion and Science. Oxford University Press.
Available online http://titan.iwu.edu/~cgillett/paper3.pdf
This paper, written with an audience in ‘Science & Religion’ in mind, provides a survey of recent notions of property emergence and the reductionist challenge that inspires them. The paper also challenges recent assumptions that we only have two coherent forms of property emergence by showing that recent problems arise from a trio of conflicting theses, rather than the pair of theses usually assumed, thus allowing for the existence of third substantive form of ‘emergence’.
◈ Gillett, Carl (Nov. 2006). Samuel Alexander's Emergentism: Or, Higher Causation for Physicalists. Synthese 153(2): 261-296.
Abstract: Samuel Alexander was one of the foremost philosophical figures of his day and has been argued by John Passmore to be one of ‘fathers’ of Australian philosophy as well as a novel kind of physicalist. Yet Alexander is now relatively neglected, his role in the genesis of Australian philosophy if far from widely accepted and the standard interpretation takes him to be an anti-physicalist. In this paper, I carefully examine these issues and show that Alexander has been badly, although understandably, misjudged by most of his contemporary critics and interpreters. Most importantly, I show that Alexander offers an ingenious, and highly original, version of physicalism at the heart of which is a strikingly different view of the nature of the microphysical properties and associated view of emergent properties. My final conclusion will be that Passmore is correct in his claims both that Alexander is significant as one of the grandfather’s of Australian philosophy and that he provides a novel physicalist position. I will also suggest that Alexander’s emergentism is important for addressing the so-called ‘problem of mental causation’ presently dogging contemporary non-reductive physicalists.
Available online http://titan.iwu.edu/~cgillett/paper4.pdf
I argue that Samuel Alexander has been misinterpreted and that he actually offers us a highly original form of physicalism as a response to a pressing form of ontological reductionism. Basically, the paper provides an outline of the positive position, in an emergentist form of physicalism I label ‘Patchwork physicalism’, which I argue is one of the few viable answers to ontological reductionism and coherent forms of non-reductive physicalism.
◈ Gillett, Carl (Forthcoming). Making Sense of Levels in the Sciences.
◈ Gillett, Carl (Forthcoming). Identity does not Protect Mental Efficacy.
◈ Gillett, Carl (Forthcoming). Ridiculous or Sublime? The Varieties of Emergence in Philosophy and the Sciences. In Gillett (ed.) Emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◈ Gillett, Carl (Forthcoming). Metaphysical Seduction and the Possibility of Strong Emergence. In Gillett (ed.) Emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◈ Gillett, Carl (ed.) (Forthcoming). Emergence: Philosophical and Scientific Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◈ Goertzel, Ben (June 2006). The Hidden Pattern: A Patternist Philosophy of Mind. Brown Walker Press.
◈ Goldstein, Jeffrey (1999). Emergence as a Construct: History and Issues. Emergence 1(1): 49-72.
◇ Gomes, Antônio, Ricardo Gudwin, Charbel Niño El-Hani and João Queiroz (in press). Towards the emergence of meaning processes in computers from Peircean semiotics. Mind & Society.
Received: 18 January 2006 Accepted: 9 October 2006 Published online: 26 April 2007
Keywords: Meaning - Semiosis - Emergence - Simulation - C. S. Peirce
◈ Grazer Philosophische Studien Volume 65. 2003. Special Issue on the topic: Mental Causation, Multiple Realization, and Emergence.
Guest Editors: Marc Slors and Sven Walter
Introduction
pp. 1-13(13)
Authors: Marc Slors; Sven Walter
Epiphenomenalism and Cross-Realization Induction
pp. 15-36(22)
Author: Marc Slors
Is Type Identity Incompatible with Multiple Realization?
pp. 37-49(13)
Author: Michael Pauen
Need Multiple Realizability Deter the Identity-Theorist?
pp. 51-75(25)
Author: Sven Walter
Emergentism, Irreducibility, and Downward Causation
pp. 77-93(17)
Author: Achim Stephan
The Varieties of Emergence: Their Purposes, Obligations and Importance
pp. 95-121(27)
Author: Carl Gillett
Causation by Relational Properties
pp. 123-137(15)
Author: Wim De Muijnck
Mental Causation: A Real Phenomenon in a Physicalistic World without Epiphenomenalism or Overdetermination
pp. 139-167(29)
Authors: Albert Newen; Rimas
uplinskas
Warum kommen "mentale Ursachen" physikalischen Erklärungen eigentlich nicht in die Quere? Einige grundsätzliche Überlegungen zur Verwendung des Ausdrucks "A verursacht B" im Umkreis moderner naturwissenschaftlicher Theorien
pp. 169-194(26)
Author: Bernd Ludwig
◈ Greyson, Bruce, Jeffrey P. Long, Kevin R. Nelson, Michelle Mattingly, Sherman A. Lee and Frederick A. Schmitt (Dec. 2006). Does the arousal system contribute to near death experience? Neurology 67: 2265.
▣ Grimes, Th. R. (1988). The myth of supervenience. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 69: 152-160.
▣ Gröblacher, Simon, Tomasz Paterek, Rainer Kaltenbaek, aslav Brukner, Marek ukowski, Markus Aspelmeyer, & Anton Zeilinger (Apr. 19, 2007). An experimental test of non-local realism. Nature 446(): 871-875.
Simon Gröblacher1,2, Tomasz Paterek3,4, Rainer Kaltenbaek1, aslav Brukner1,2, Marek ukowski1,3, Markus Aspelmeyer1,2 & Anton Zeilinger1,2
doi:10.1038/nature05677; Received 22 December 2006; Accepted 13 February 2007
Most working scientists hold fast to the concept of 'realism'—a viewpoint according to which an external reality exists independent of observation. But quantum physics has shattered some of our cornerstone beliefs. According to Bell's theorem, any theory that is based on the joint assumption of realism and locality (meaning that local events cannot be affected by actions in space-like separated regions) is at variance with certain quantum predictions. Experiments with entangled pairs of particles have amply confirmed these quantum predictions, thus rendering local realistic theories untenable. Maintaining realism as a fundamental concept would therefore necessitate the introduction of 'spooky' actions that defy locality. Here we show by both theory and experiment that a broad and rather reasonable class of such non-local realistic theories is incompatible with experimentally observable quantum correlations. In the experiment, we measure previously untested correlations between two entangled photons, and show that these correlations violate an inequality proposed by Leggett for non-local realistic theories. Our result suggests that giving up the concept of locality is not sufficient to be consistent with quantum experiments, unless certain intuitive features of realism are abandoned.
☞ see Philip Ball's review of this article: Physicists bid farewell to reality?
http://www.nature/com/news/2007/070416/full/070416-9.html
☞ see also Scientific American's Science News by J.R. Minkel: Quantum Theory Fails Reality Checks.
http://www.sciam.com/article.cfm?articleID=055C1A23-E7F2-99DF-31B2170DBBCA09A9&chanID=sa003
FOR REAL? A new experiment on photons sharing the quantum link of entanglement finds that quantum naysayers have to give up two cherished principles of reality, not one or the other.
Image: © ISTOCKPHOTO.COM/DUNCAN WALKER
◇ Gustafson, Don (June 2007). Neurosciences of Action and Noncausal Theories. Philosophical Psychology 20(3): 367-374.
Abstract: Recent neuroscience and psychology of behavior have suggested that conscious decisions may have no causal role in the etiology of intentional action. Such results pose a threat to traditional philosophical analyses of action. On such views beliefs, desires and conscious willing are part of the causal structure of intentional action. But if the suggestions from neuroscience/psychology are correct, analyses of this kind are wrong. Conscious antecedents of action are epiphenomenal. This essay explores this consequence. It also notes that the traditional alternative to causal analyses of intentional action is not threatened by the putative scientific findings. This, in turn, is ironic in that defenders of the noncausal accounts of action were thought to be in opposition to the natural sciences of action whereas the analyses in the causal style were "on the side of physicalism." This result is also assessed in what follows.
Keywords: Conscious Will; Epiphenomenalism; Intentional Action; Neuroscience; Noncausal Theories of Action
◈ Habermas, Jürgen / Translated by Joel Anderson (Mar. 2007). The Language Game of Responsible Agency and the Problem of Free Will: How can epistemic dualism be reconciled with ontological monism? Philosophical Explorations 10(1): 13-50.
Abstract: In this essay, I address the question of whether the indisputable progress being made by the neurosciences poses a genuine threat to the language game of responsible agency. I begin by situating free will as an ineliminable component of our practices of attributing responsibility and holding one another accountable, illustrating this via a discussion of legal discourse regarding the attribution of responsibility for criminal acts. I then turn to the practical limits on agents' scientific self-objectivation, limits that turn out to be mirrored philosophically in the conceptual problems that plague reductionist strategies. Having shown that free will is rooted in unavoidable performative presuppositions belonging to agents' participant perspective, I then take up the difficult issue of how to reconcile an epistemic dualism of participant and observer perspectives with the assumption of ontological monism. I critically review a range of proposed physicalist solutions, including non-reductionist and (standard) compatibilist approaches. An underlying problem with scientistic, physicalist approaches is the methodological fiction of an exclusive 'view from nowhere' which relies on the problematic move of disengaging the objectivating perspective of the scientific observer from the investigators' participant perspective of those engaged in scientific practice. Since there is no way of getting around the requisite complementarity of both the observer's encounter with the objective world and the participant's involvement in shared lifeworld practices, the remaining option is to take an epistemological turn. But even the recognition that science is ultimately constituted from within the lifeworld still leaves us with the question as to how the human mind can understand itself as the product of natural evolution. I conclude with some tentative suggestions as to how this difficult question might be addressed.
Keywords: free will; compatibilism; physicalism; scientism; participant perspective; performative presuppositions
http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/ftinterface~content=a774762029~fulltext=713240930
☞ see John Searle's reply (Mar. 2007).
◇ Häggström, Olle (Mar. 2007). Intelligent design and the NFL theorems. Biology and Philosophy 22(2): 217-230.
Received: 14 September 2005 Accepted: 15 June 2006 Published online: 13 December 2006
Key words: Optimization - NFL theorem - Fitness landscape - Intelligent design - Local search - Uniform distribution
◈ Haken, Hermann (2004). Synergetics: Introduction and advanced topics. Berlin: Springer.
◈ Haken, Hermann (2002/2007). Brain dynamics: Synchronization and activity patterns in pulse-coupled neural nets with delays and noise. (Springer series in Synergetics). Berlin: Springer.
◈ Haken, Hermann (2006). Information and self-organization: A macroscopic approach to complex systems. (Springer Series in Synergetics). Berlin: Springer.
◈ Haken, Hermann (2007). Synergetics. Scholarpedia. p.7017.
◆ Haldane, John (1996). The mystery of emergence. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 96: 261-267.
◈ Halley, Julianne D. and David A. Winkler (undated). Classification of emergence and its relation to self-organization.
Abstract: Emergence is a difficult concept to describe clearly. It has been characterized in the literature in a number of ways, none of which are easy to understand or describe clearly how other concepts in complex systems science are related to emergence. We provide a simple, clear description and classification of emergence in terms of self-organization. This provides a framework for understanding how concepts such as thermodynamic equilibrium, nonlinearity, and computability are related to emergence.
Keywords: Emergence; self-organization; predictive efficiency; observer.
◈ Halley, Julianne D. and David A. Winkler (forthcoming). Towards consistent concepts of self-organization and self-assembly, submitted to PNAS.
▣ Hameroff, Stuart R. and Roger Penrose (Apr. 1996). Orchestrated reduction of quantum coherence in brain microtubules. Mathematics and Computers in Simulation 40(3-4): 453-480.
◈ Hameroff, Stuart R. (Apr. 1998). 'Funda-Mentality': is the conscious mind subtly linked to a basic level of the universe? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 2(4): 119-124.
◈ Hameroff, Stuart R. (Aug. 15, 1998). Quantum computation in brain microtubules?: The Penrose-Hameroff 'Orch OR' model of consciousness. Phil. Trans. Roy. Soc. Lond. A 356(1743): 1869-1896.
◈ Hameroff, Stuart R. (Apr. 2001). Consciousness, the brain, and spacetime geometry. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 929(1): 74-104.
◈ Hameroff, Stuart R. (June 1, 2001). Anesthesia: the "other side" of consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition 10(2): 217-229.
◈ Hameroff, Stuart R. (2002). Quantum computing in DNA.
http://www.consciousness.arizona.edu/hameroff
◈ Hameroff, Stuart R. (Aug. 2006). The Entwined Mysteries of Anesthesia and Consciousness: Is There a Common Underlying Mechanism? Anesthesiology 105(2): 400–12.
▣ Hameroff, Stuart R. (Mar. 2007). Orchestrated Reduction of Quantum Coherence in Brain Microtubules: A Model for Consciousness. NeuroQuantology 5(1): 1-8.
Abstract: Orch OR (“Orchestrated Objective Reduction”) is a theory of consciousness put forth in the mid-1990s by British physicist Sir Roger Penrose and American anesthesiologist Stuart Hameroff. Whereas most theories assume consciousness emerges from complex computation at the level of synapses among brain neurons, Orch OR involves a specific form of quantum computation which underlies these neuronal synaptic activities. The proposed quantum computations occur in structures inside the brain’s neurons called microtubules.
Key Words: consciousness, microtubules, computation, neurons, orchestrated objective reduction
CONCLUSION: Orch OR can account for all enigmatic features of consciousness including timing, binding, pre-conscious to conscious transition and the hard problem of conscious experience. Orch OR is consistent with all known neurophysiology, but depends on proposed physics and biology. Orch OR has withstood numerous attempts at refutation, and is testable and falsifiable. Although controversial, it is the most complete theory of consciousness, spanning in detail physics, molecular biology, neuroscience, cognitive science and philosophy.
☞ see A Severe Criticism by Georgiev, Danko Dimchev (Mar. 2007). Falsifications of Hameroff-Penrose Orch OR Model of Consciousness and Novel Avenues for Development of Quantum Mind Theory. NeuroQuantology 5(1): 145-174. www.neuroquantology.com
◈ Hameroff, Stuart R. (in press). The brain is both neurocomputer and quantum computer. Cognitive Science.
http://www.quantumconsciousness.org/cogsci.htm
☞ see Abninder Litt and his collaborators' criticism of Stuart Hameroff's theory of quantum consciousness.
◈ Hameroff, Stuart R., Alex Nip, Mitchell Porter, Jack Tuszynski (Jan. 2002). Conduction pathways in microtubules, biological quantum computation, and consciousness. BioSystems 64(1-3): 149-168.
◆ Hasker, William (1982). Emergentism. Religious Studies 18: 473-88.
◆ Hasker, William (1999). The Emergent Self. Cornell University Press.
◈ Hattiangadi, Jagdish N. (2005). The Emergence of Minds in Space and Time. In David Martel Johnson and Christina E. Erneling eds. The Mind as a Scientific Object: Between Brain and Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◈ Hauser, Marc D., Noam Chomsky, W. Tecumseh Fitch (Nov. 2002). The faculty of language: What is it, Who has it, and How did it evolve? Science 298(5598): 1569-1579 (Issue of Nov. 22, 2002).
We argue that an understanding of the faculty of language requires substantial interdisciplinary cooperation. We suggest how current developments in linguistics can be profitably wedded to work in evolutionary biology, anthropology, psychology, and neuroscience. We submit that a distinction should be made between the faculty of language in the broad sense (FLB) and in the narrow sense (FLN). FLB includes a sensory-motor system, a conceptual-intentional system, and the computational mechanisms for recursion, providing the capacity to generate an infinite range of expressions from a finite set of elements. We hypothesize that FLN only includes recursion and is the only uniquely human component of the faculty of language. We further argue that FLN may have evolved for reasons other than language, hence comparative studies might look for evidence of such computations outside of the domain of communication (for example, number, navigation, and social relations).
☞ see Thomas Bever and Mario Montalbetti's review of this paper.
◈ Hayek, Friedrich August von (1964). The theory of complex phenomena. In: The critical approach to science and technology (In honor of Karl R. Popper). (Ed. Mario Bunge). The Free Press of Glencoe. pp. 332-349.
Friedrich August von Hayek (May 8, 1899 - Mar. 23, 1992)
◈ Heard, Daniel (Jan. 2006). A new problem for ontological emergence. The Philosophical Quarterly 56(222): 55-62.
It is becoming increasingly common to find phenomena described as emergent. There are two sorts of philosophical analysis of emergence. Ontological analyses ground emergence in real, distinct, emergent properties. Epistemological analyses deny emergent properties and stress instead facts about our epistemic status. I review a standard worry for ontological analyses of emergence, that they entail a surfeit of metaphysics, and find that it can easily be sidestepped. I go on to present a new worry, that ontological emergentism entails a highly implausible ontology, which is harder for the ontological emergentist to avoid.
◈ Heil, John (1998). Supervenience deconstructed. European Journal of Philosophy 6: 146-155.
◈ Heil, John (2000). Multiple Realizability. American Philosophical Quarterly 36: 189-208.
◇ Hein, Hilde (Aug. 1969). Molecular biology vs. organicism: The enduring dispute between mechanism and vitalism. Synthese 20(2): 238-253.
◈ Hellman, Geoffrey, and Frank Thompson (1975). Physicalism: Ontology, Determination, Reduction. The Journal of Philosophy 72: 551 564.
◈ Hendel, Giovanna (2001). Realization. Crítica, Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía, Vol. 33, No. 98, August 2001, pp. 41-70.
http://critica.filosoficas.unam.mx/pdf/C98/C98_hendel.pdf
Abstract: So far no clear explication of the notion of realization has been offered, in spite of the frequent uses of the notion in the literature to discharge import!ant jobs, such as that of accounting for the causal efficacy of the mental in a physical world, and that of providing a viable characterization of physicalism, and/or psychophysical reduction. I put forward an account of realization as an identity-like relation. I argue that such account has the following advantages: (a) it provides a picture under which it makes sense to use the same term, i.e. 'realization', to pick out relations that differ in their relata, as it happened in the original uses of the term 'realization'; (b) it helps to understand how well, if at all, some appeals to realization in the literature can discharge the jobs mentioned; (c) more generally, it makes clear what realization can do.
Keywords: realization, identity-like, reduction, mental causation, physicalism
◈ Hendrey, Robin Findlay (1999). Molecular models and the question of physicalism. HYLE―International Journal for Philosophy of Chemistry 5(2): 117-134.
Abstract: By their own account, physicalists are committed to the claim that physics is causally complete, or closed. The claim is presented as an empirical one. However, detailed and explicit empirical arguments for the claim are rare. I argue that molecular models are a key source of evidence but that, on closer inspection, they do not support the completeness claim.
Keywords: chemistry, physicalism, reductionism, supervenience, disunity of science.
■ Hendry, Robin Findlay (2006). Is There Downward Causation in Chemistry? Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 242 (Philosophy Of Chemistry: Synthesis of a New Discipline, edited by Davis Baird, Eric Scerri and Lee McIntyre): 173-189. (doi:10.1007/1-4020-3261-7_9)
First paragraph:
Unless the future of chemistry holds some great ontological revision, it seems safe to assume that whenever there is chemical change there is physical change. For instance, on the assumption that an object’s membership of a natural kind is determined by its possession of certain physical properties, there cannot be change in chemical kind membership without change in these kind-constituting physical properties. There is a consensus in recent philosophy of mind that this kind of relationship—known as supervenience—is, however, compatible with a range of views on the ontological relationship between two domains.1 It is, for instance, a commitment both of physicalism—the view that physical laws and facts determine all laws and facts—and of some forms of emergentism, the view that there are autonomous facts associated with the physical systems of higher orders of complexity studied by some of the special sciences.
■ Hendry, Robin Findlay and Paul Needham (in press. published online on Apr. 30, 2007). Le Poidevin on the Reduction of Chemistry. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
In this article we critically evaluate Robin Le Poidevin's recent attempt to set out an argument for the ontological reduction of chemistry independently of intertheoretic reduction. We argue, firstly, that the argument he envisages applies only to a small part of chemistry, and that there is no obvious way to extend it. We argue, secondly, that the argument cannot establish the reduction of chemistry, properly so called.
◆ Henle, Paul (Aug. 27, 1942). The Status of Emergence. The Journal of Philosophy 39(18): 486-493.
The doctrine of emergence, having passed through the stage of acute philosophic controversy, has become to a large extent a generally accepted view. Unfortunately it has not become an unambiguous view. In one sense it seems to amount to no more than the insistence that there are novelties in the world. If this is all that is intended, the doctrine is a corollary of evolutionary theory and there can be little doubt as to its truth. To take a simple case, color vision can have appeared in the world only with the development of animal life and there must have been a first animal capable of distinguishing, say, the color violet. There might be variations in the clarity with which violet is distinguished, but, allowing for such differences, the statement stands. This color of violet, in its purely qualitative aspects as it appeared to the primitive animal, must have been something new under the sun.
◈ Hensel, Michael, Achim Menges, Michael Weinstock (eds.) (2004). Emergence: Morphogenetic Design Strategies (Architectural Design). Academy Press.
◈ Himma, Kenneth Einar (2005). What is a problem for all is a problem for none: Substance
dualism, physicalism, and the mind-body problem. American Philosophical Quarterly
42: 81-92.
◈ Hofstadter, Douglas R. (Mar. 26, 2007). I Am a Strange Loop. Basic Books.
◈ Holland, John H. (1998). Emergence: From Chaos to Order. Oxford University Press.
▣ Hood, Leroy and David Galas (Jan. 2003). The digital code of DNA. Nature 421(6921): 444-448 (Issue of Jan. 23, 2003).
The discovery of the structure of DNA transformed biology profoundly, catalysing the sequencing of the human genome and engendering a new view of biology as an information science. Two features of DNA structure account for much of its remarkable impact on science: its digital nature and its complementarity, whereby one strand of the helix binds perfectly with its partner. DNA has two types of digital information — the genes that encode proteins, which are the molecular machines of life, and the gene regulatory networks that specify the behaviour of the genes.
▣ Hooker, Clifford Alan (1981). Towards a general theory of reduction. Dialogue 20: 38-60, 201-236, 496-529.
◈ Hooker, Clifford Alan (2004). Asymptotics, Reduction and Emergence. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55(3):435-479.
All the major inter-theoretic relations of fundamental science are asymptotic ones, e.g. quantum theory as Planck's constant h 0, yielding (roughly) Newtonian mechanics. Thus asymptotics ultimately grounds claims about inter-theoretic explanation, reduction and emergence. This paper examines four recent, central claims by Batterman concerning asymptotics and reduction. While these claims are criticised, the discussion is used to develop an enriched, dynamically-based account of reduction and emergence, to show its capacity to illuminate the complex variety of inter-theory relationships in physics, and to provide a principled resolution to such persistent philosophical problems as multiple realisability and the nature of the special sciences.
C. A. Hooker
School of Liberal Arts, MCLG27, University of Newcastle, Callaghan, NSW, Australia 2308,
http://www.newcastle.edu.au/centre/casrg/index.html
◈ Horgan, Terence (1993). From Supervenience to Superdupervenience: Meeting the Demands of a Material World. Mind 102: 555-86.
First paragraph:
The term "supervenience" derives etymologically from the Latin "super", meaning on, above, or additional; and from the Latin verb "venire", meaning to come. In non-philosophical contexts the word is used primarily in a temporal way—typically to mean "coming or occurring as something novel, additional, or unexpected". In philosophical contexts it is primarily used non-temporally, to signify a metaphysical and/or conceptual determination-relation; here the etymology appears to be spatially quasi-metaphorical, the idea being that something supervenient comes above—is "grounded by"—that on which it supervenes.
◈ Horgan, Terence, Marcelo H. Sabates and David Sosa (eds.) (forthcoming). Supervenience in Mind: A Festschrift in honor of Jaegwon Kim. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
▣ Hoyningen-Huene, Paul (1994). Zu Emergenz, Mikro- und Makrodetermination. In Weyma Lübbe (ed.) (1994). Kausalität und Zurechnung. Über Verantwortung in komplexen kulturellen Prozessen. Berlin, New York: Walter de Gruyter. PDF
▣ Hoyning-Huene, Paul (1997). Comment on J. Kim's "Supervenience, Emergence, and Realization in the Philosophy of Mind". In: Martin Carrier and Peter Machamer (eds.) Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind (Pittsburgh-Konstanz Series in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol. 5), Universitätsverlag Konstanz/University of Pittsburgh Press,1997, pp. 294-302. PDF
http://www.nunics.uni-hannover.de/zeww/074_Hoyningen_Comment_Kim.pdf
◈ Hulswit, Menno (2005). How Causal is Downward Causation? Journal for General Philosophy of Science 36(2): 261-287.
Published online: 14 August 2006
Key words: Aristotelian categories - causation - causal relata - downward causation - emergence - self-organization - formal causation
◆ Humphreys, Paul (1996). Aspects of emergence. Philosophical Topics 24:53-71.
◈ Humphreys, Paul (Mar. 1997). How Properties Emerge. Philosophy of science 64(1):1-17.
A framework for representing a specific kind of emergent property instance is given. A solution to a generalized version of the exclusion argument is then provided and it is shown that upwards and downwards causation is unproblematical for that kind of emergence. One real example of this kind of emergence is briefly described and the suggestion made that emergence may be more common than current opinions allow.
◈ Humphreys, Paul (Dec. 1997). Emergence, not supervenience. Philosophy of Science 64 (Supplement. Proceedings of the 1996 Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part II: Symposia Papers): S337-S345.
I argue that supervenience is an inadequate device for representing relations between different levels of phenomena. I then provide six criteria that emergent phenomena seem to satisfy. Using examples drawn from macroscopic physics, I suggest that such emergent features may well be quite common in the physical realm.
◆ Humphreys, Paul (to appear). Synchronic and Diachronic Emergence. Minds and Machines.
◈ Hunt, G.M.K. (June 1987). Determinism, predictability and chaos. Analysis 47(3): 129-133.
☞ see Morton (June 1988).
◈ Hut, Piet, Mark Alford and Max Tegmark (June 2006). On Math, Matter and Mind. Foundations of Physics 36(6): 765-794.
▣ Hüttemann, Andreas (Dec. 2003). What's Wrong With Microphysicalism? Routledge.
Acknowledgements | ||
Introduction | 1 | |
1 | Microphysicalism | 5 |
2 | Laws of nature | 16 |
3 | Micro-explanation | 24 |
4 | What is the issue? | 58 |
5 | Micro-determination | 71 |
6 | Micro-government and the laws of the special sciences | 87 |
7 | Micro-causation | 107 |
8 | Microphysicalism, physicalism and pluralism | 120 |
Notes | 127 | |
Bibliography | 134 | |
Index |
About the Title
'Microphysicalism', the view that whole objects behave the way they do in virtue of the behaviour of their constituent parts, is an influential contemporary view with a long philosophical and scientific heritage. In What's Wrong With Microphysicalism? Andreas Hütemann offers a fresh challenge to this view.
Hütemann agrees with the microphysicalists that we can explain compound systems by explaining their parts, but claims that this does not entail a fundamentalism that gives hegemony to the micro-level. At most, it shows that there is a relationship of determination between parts and wholes, but there is no justification for taking this relationship to be asymmetrical rather than one of mutual dependence. H?temann argues that if this is the case, then microphysicalists have no right to claim that the micro-level is the ultimate agent: neither the parts nor the whole have 'ontological priority'. H?temann advocates a pragmatic pluralism, allowing for different ways to describe nature.
What's Wrong With Microphysicalism? is a convincing and original contribution to central issues in contemporary philosophy of mind, philosophy of science and metaphysics.
▣ Hüttemann, Andreas (2004). On the prospects of confined and catholic physicalism. In: Roland Bluhm & Christian Nimtz (Hgg.) (2004). Ausgewählte Beiträge zu den Sektionen der GAP.5, Fünfter Internationaler Kongress der Gesellschaft für Analytische Philosophie, Bielefeld, 22.–26. September 2003. (CD-ROM) Paderborn: mentis. S. 396 – 405.
◈ Hüttemann, Andreas (Jan. 2005). Explanation, emergence, and quantum entanglement. Philosophy of Science 72(1): 114-127.
Received April 2003; revised February 2004.
Abstract: This paper tries to get a grip on two seemingly conflicting intuitions about reductionism in quantum mechanics. On one hand it is received wisdom that quantum mechanics puts an end to `reductionism'. Quantum entanglement is responsible for such features of quantum mechanics as holism, the failure of supervenience, and emergence. While I agree with these claims, I will argue that it is only part of the story. Quantum mechanics provides us with thoroughgoing reductionist explanations. I will distinguish two kinds of microexplanation (or micro-`reduction'). I will argue that even though quantum entanglement provides an example of the failure of one kind of microexplanation, it does not affect the other. Contrary to a recent paper by Kronz and Tiehen, I claim that the explanation of the dynamics of quantum mechanical systems is just as reductionist as it used to be in classical mechanics.
▣ Hüttemann, Andreas (2007). Causation, Laws and Dispositions In: Max Kistler and Bruno Gnassounou (eds.) (2007). Dispositions and Causal Powers. Aldershot: Ashgate, pp. 207 – 219.
◈ Hüttemann, Andreas and David Papineau (Jan. 2005). Physicalism decomposed. Analysis 65(1): 33-39.
http://wwwphil.uni-muenster.de/mitglieder/huettemann/texte/Physicalism_decomposed.pdf
◈ Hütteman, Andreas & Orestis Terzidis (2000). Emergence in Physics. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14(3): 267-281.
◈ Intellectica (Revue de l'Association pour la Recherche Cognitive Publiée avec le concours du CNRS) 1997/3, numéro 25.
A special issue on Emergence and Explication.
◈ Israeli, Navot, Nigel Goldenfeld (2004). Computational Irreducibility and the Predictability of Complex Physical Systems. Physical Review Letters 92(7), 074105.
(Received 16 June 2003; published 20 February 2004)
Abstract: Using elementary cellular automata (CA) as an example, we show how to coarse grain CA in all classes of Wolfram's classification. We find that computationally irreducible physical processes can be predictable and even computationally reducible at a coarse-grained level of description. The resulting coarse-grained CA which we construct emulate the large-scale behavior of the original systems without accounting for small-scale details. At least one of the CA that can be coarse grained is irreducible and known to be a universal Turing machine.
http://arxiv.org/pdf/nlin/0309047
◈ Jacobs, Gerald H., Gary A. Williams, Hugh Cahill and Jeremy Nathans (Mar. 2007). Emergence of Novel Color Vision in Mice Engineered to Express a Human Cone Photopigment. Science 315(5819): 1723-1725 (Issue of March 23, 2007).
Changes in the genes encoding sensory receptor proteins are an essential step in the evolution of new sensory capacities. In primates, trichromatic color vision evolved after changes in X chromosome–linked photopigment genes. To model this process, we studied knock-in mice that expressed a human long-wavelength–sensitive (L) cone photopigment in the form of an X-linked polymorphism. Behavioral tests demonstrated that heterozygous females, whose retinas contained both native mouse pigments and human L pigment, showed enhanced long-wavelength sensitivity and acquired a new capacity for chromatic discrimination. An inherent plasticity in the mammalian visual system thus permits the emergence of a new dimension of sensory experience based solely on gene-driven changes in receptor organization.
《사이언티픽 아메리칸Scientific Amerian》해설 기사 ☞
http://www.sciam.com/article.cfm?articleid=7B502B4F-E7F2-99DF-3ADC02BA5D5721F0&chanId=sa017
|
◈ Jaworski, William (Sep. 2006). Mental causation from the top-down. Erkenntnis 65(2): 277-299.
◆ Jones, D. H. (1972). Emergent properties, persons, and the mind-body problem. Southern Journal of Philosophy 10: 423-433.
◈ Juarrero, Alicia (1999). Dynamics in Action: Intentional Behavior as a Complex System. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press.
◈ Kallestrup, Jesper (Nov. 2006). The causal exclusion argument. Philosophical Studies 131(2): 459-485.
◈ Kauffman, Stuart A. (1993). The Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution. Oxford University Press.
◈ Kauffman, Stuart A. (1996). At Home in the Universe: The Search for the Laws of Self-Organization and Complexity. Oxford University Press.
◈ Kauffman, Stuart A. (2000). Investigations. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
▣ Kauffman Stuart A. (2006). The third culture beyond reductionism: reinventing the sacred. Edge.org, November 20, 2006.
◈ Kauffman, Stuart A. and Philip Clayton (2006). On emergence, agency, and organization. Biology and Philosophy 21(4): 501-521.
Received: 16 July 2004 Accepted: 26 July 2005 Published online: 15 November 2006
Keywords: Autocatalysis - Autonomous agents - Emergence - Preadaptation - Reductionism - Theory of organization - Semiotics - Teleology - Underdetermination of biology by physics - Work cycle
▣ Kauffman, Stuart A., Robert K. Logan, Robert Este, Randy Goebel, David Hobill and Ilya Shmulevich (in press. Mar. 20, 2007). Propagating organization: An enquiry. Biology and Philosophy.
Received: 2 January 2007 Accepted: 19 February 2007 Published online: 20 March 2007
Abstract: Our aim in this article is to attempt to discuss propagating organization of process, a poorly articulated union of matter, energy, work, constraints and that vexed concept, “information”, which unite in far from equilibrium living physical systems. Our hope is to stimulate discussions by philosophers of biology and biologists to further clarify the concepts we discuss here. We place our discussion in the broad context of a “general biology”, properties that might well be found in life anywhere in the cosmos, freed from the specific examples of terrestrial life after 3.8 billion years of evolution. By placing the discussion in this wider, if still hypothetical, context, we also try to place in context some of the extant discussion of information as intimately related to DNA, RNA and protein transcription and translation processes. While characteristic of current terrestrial life, there are no compelling grounds to suppose the same mechanisms would be involved in any life form able to evolve by heritable variation and natural selection. In turn, this allows us to discuss at least briefly, the focus of much of the philosophy of biology on population genetics, which, of course, assumes DNA, RNA, proteins, and other features of terrestrial life. Presumably, evolution by natural selection—and perhaps self-organization—could occur on many worlds via different causal mechanisms. Here we seek a non-reductionist explanation for the synthesis, accumulation, and propagation of information, work, and constraint, which we hope will provide some insight into both the biotic and abiotic universe, in terms of both molecular self reproduction and the basic work energy cycle where work is the constrained release of energy into a few degrees of freedom. The typical requirement for work itself is to construct those very constraints on the release of energy that then constitute further work. Information creation, we argue, arises in two ways: first information as natural selection assembling the very constraints on the release of energy that then constitutes work and the propagation of organization. Second, information in a more extended sense is “semiotic”, that is about the world or internal state of the organism and requires appropriate response. The idea is to combine ideas from biology, physics, and computer science, to formulate explanatory hypotheses on how information can be captured and rendered in the expected physical manifestation, which can then participate in the propagation of the organization of process in the expected biological work cycles to create the diversity in our observable biosphere. Our conclusions, to date, of this enquiry suggest a foundation which views information as the construction of constraints, which, in their physical manifestation, partially underlie the processes of evolution to dynamically determine the fitness of organisms within the context of a biotic universe.
Keywords: Propagating organization - Constraints - Information - Shannon - Work - Semiosis - Adjacent possible
An organized being is then not a mere machine, for that has merely moving power, but it possesses in itself formative power of a self-propagating kind which it communicates to its materials though they have it not of themselves; it organizes them, in fact, and this cannot explained by the mere mechanical faculty of motion.
Immanuel Kant – Critique of Judgement.
◈ Ke, Jinyun and John H. Holland (2006). Language Origin from an Emergentist Perspective. Applied Linguistics 27(4):691-716.
Abstract: In recent decades, there has been a surge of interest in the origin of language across a wide range of disciplines. Emergentism provides a new perspective to integrate investigations from different areas of study. This paper discusses how the study of language acquisition can contribute to the inquiry, in particular when computer modeling is adopted as the research methodology. An agent-based model is described as an illustration, which simulates how word order in a language could have emerged at the very beginning of language origin. Two important features of emergence, heterogeneity and nonlinearity, are demonstrated in the model, and their implications for applied linguistics are discussed.
☞ see Brian MacWhinney's paper that deals with the emergence of language.
◈ Keijzer, Fred, Maurice Schouten (in press). Embedded Cognition and Mental Causation: Setting Empirical Bounds on Metaphysics. Synthese.
◈ Kekes, John (1966). Physicalism, the identity theory, and the concept of emergence. Philosophy of Science 33: 360-375.
◈ Kelso, J.A. Scott (1995). Dynamic Patterns: The Self-Organization of Brain and Behavior. Cambridge,MA: The MIT Press.
▣ Kim, Jaegwon (1976). Events as Property Exemplifications. In: M. Brand & D. Walton (eds.) Action Theory (pp. 157–177). Dordrecht: Reidel. Reprinted in Kim (1993b).
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (1978). Supervenience and Nomological Incommensurables. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15: 149–56.
▣ Kim, Jaegwon (1984a). Epiphenomenal and Supervenient Causation. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9:257–270. Reprinted in Kim (1993b).
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (1984b). Concepts of Supervenience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 153-76. Reprinted pp. 53-78 in Kim 1993.
▣ Kim, Jaegwon (1988). Explanatory Realism, Causal Realism, and Explanatory Exclusion. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12: 225–240.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (1989). Mechanism, Purpose, and Explanatory Exclusion. Philosophical Perspectives 3: 77-108. Reprinted pp. 237-264. in Kim 1993.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (1989). The Myth of Nonreductive Materialism. (Presidential address delivered at the meeting of the American Philosophical Association, the Central Division, April, 1989). Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 63: 31-47.
▣ Kim, Jaegwon (1990a). Explanatory Exclusion and the Problem of Mental Causation. In: E. Villanueva (ed.) Information, Semantics, and Epistemology (pp. 36–56). Oxford: Blackwell.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (1990b). Supervenience as a Philosophical Concept. (the Metaphilosophy Address delivered at the Graduate Center, CUNY, May, 1989). Metaphilosophy 12: 1-27. Reprinted pp. 131-160 in Kim 1993.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (1992a). 'Downward Causation' in Emergentism and Nonreductive Physicalism. Published pp. 119-138 in Beckermann, Ansgar, Hans Flohr, Jaegwon Kim (eds.) Emergence or Reduction? - Essays on the Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (1992b). Multiple Realization and the Metaphysics of Reduction. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52: 1-26.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (1993a). The Nonreductivist's Troubles with Mental Causation. Published in John Heil and Alfred Mele (eds.) Mental Causation. Oxford University Press.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (1993b). Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (1997). Supervenience, Emergence, and Realization. Published pp. 271-293 in: Martin Carrier and Peter K. Machamer (eds.) Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science and the Mind. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. (with commentaries by Paul Hoyningen-Huene and Ansgar Beckermann).
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (1997). Explanation, Prediction, and Reduction in Emergentism. Intellectica 2: 27-38.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (1998). Mind in a Physical World: An Essay on the Mind-Body Problem and Mental Causation. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (Aug. 1999). Making Sense of Emergence. Philosophical Studies 95(1-2): 3-36.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (2000). Making Sense of Downward Causation. Published pp. 305-321 in: Peter Bøgh Andersen, Claus Emmeche, Niels Ole Finnemann and Peder Voetmann Christiansen (eds.) (2000). Downward Causation: Minds, bodies and matter. Aarhus: Aarhus University Press.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (2001). Mental Causation and Consciousness: The Two Mind-body Problems for the Physicalist. Published in: Carl Gillett and Barry Loewer (eds.) Physicalism and Its Discontents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (2002). The Layered Model: Metaphysical Considerations. Philosophical Explorations 5: 2-20.
▣ Kim, Jaegwon (ed.) (Aug. 2002). Supervenience (The International Research Library of Philosophy). Aldershot: Ashgate.
Acknowledgements | ||
Series Preface | ||
Introduction | ||
1 | Physicalism: Ontology, Determination, and Reduction | 1 |
2 | Supervenience Revisited | 15 |
3 | Concepts of Supervenience | 37 |
4 | Supervenience for Multiple Domains | 63 |
5 | Postscripts on Supervenience | 85 |
6 | Supervenience and Microphysics | 97 |
7 | From Supervenience to Superdupervenience: Meeting the Demands of a Material World | 113 |
8 | Varieties of Supervenience | 145 |
9 | Varieties of Supervenience | 189 |
10 | Supervenience: Ontological and Ascriptive | 211 |
11 | "Global" Supervenient Determination: Too Permissive? | 221 |
12 | In Defense of Global Supervenience | 249 |
13 | Supervenience, Necessary Coextension, and Reducibility | 271 |
14 | Supervenience and Closure | 285 |
15 | The Myth of Supervenience | 299 |
16 | Humean Supervenience | 309 |
17 | An Argument for Strong Supervenience | 317 |
18 | Arguments for Supervenience and Physical Realization | 325 |
19 | Against the Doctrine of Microphysical Supervenience | 343 |
20 | Moral Supervenience | 357 |
21 | Supervenience, Essentialism and Aesthetic Properties | 381 |
Name Index | 397 |
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (2003). Supervenience, Emergence, Realization, Reduction. Published in: Michael J. Loux, Dean W. Zimmerman (eds.) The Oxford Handbook on Metaphysics. Oxford University Press.
▣ Kim, Jaegwon (2003). Blocking Causal Drainage and other Maintenance Chores with Mental Causation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67:151–176.
■ Kim, Jaegwon (2005). Physicalism, Or Somthing Near Enough. Princeton University Press.
Table of contents
Ch. 1 | Mental causation and consciousness : our two mind-body problems | 7 |
Ch. 2 | The supervenience argument motivated, clarified, and defended | 32 |
Ch. 3 | The rejection of immaterial minds : a causal argument | 70 |
Ch. 4 | Reduction, reductive explanation, and closing the "gap" | 93 |
Ch. 5 | Explanatory arguments for type physicalism and why they don't work | 121 |
Ch. 6 | Physicalism, or something near enough | 149 |
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (2005). Philosophy of Mind. 2nd edition. Boulder: Westview Press.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (2006). Being Realistic about Emergence. Published in: Clayton, Philip, Paul Davies (eds.) The Re-Emergence of Emergence: The Emergentist Hypothesis from Science to Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◈ Kim, Jaegwon (2006). Emergence: Core Ideas and Issues. Synthese 151(3): 547-559.
Published online: 9 August 2006
Keywords: Downward causation - Emergence - Emergentism - Reduction - Supervenience
Published online: 8 August 2006
Keywords: Aggregativity - Causal power - Emergence - Functional reduction - Inter-level - Intra-level - Multirealization - Reduction - Second-order predicate
▣ Kistler, Max and Bruno Gnassounou (eds.) (Feb. 2007). Dispositions and Causal Powers. Aldershot: Ashgate.
About the Book
Dispositions are everywhere. We say that a wall is hard, that water quenches thirst and is transparent, that dogs can swim and oak trees can let their leaves fall, and that acid has the power to corrode metals. All these statements express attributions of dispositions, be they physical, physiological or psychological, yet there is much philosophical debate about how far, if at all, dispositional predicates can have complete
meaning or figure in causal explanations.
This collection of essays, by leading international researchers, examine the case for realism with respect to dispositions and causal powers in both metaphysics and science. Among the issues debated in this book is whether dispositions can be analyzed in terms of conditionals, whether all dispositions have a so-called categorical basis and, if they do, what is the relation between the disposition and its basis.
Contents
Part 1 The Metaphysics of Dispositions and Causal Powers:
Dispositions and counterfactuals. From Carnap to Goodman's children and grandchildren, François Schmitz
Filled in space, Stephen Mumford
Dispositions and essences, Claudine Tiercelin
The causal efficacy of macroscopic dispositional properties, Max Kistler
Opium's virtus dormitiva, Cyrille Michon
Conditional possibility, Bruno Gnassounou
On ascribing dispositions, Ludger Jansen
Part 2 Dispositions and Causal Powers in Science:
An extended semantic field of dispositions and the grounding role of causal powers, Rom Harré
What makes a capacity a disposition?, Nancy Cartwright
Causation, laws and dispositions, Andreas Hüttemann
Can capacities rescue us from Ceteris Paribus laws?, Markus Schrenk
Dispositions, relational properties and the quantum world, Mauro Dorato
Are specific heats dispositions?, Anouk Barberousse
Bibliography
Index
◈ Klee, Robert L. (Mar. 1984). Micro-Determinism and Concepts of Emergence. Philosophy of Science 51(1): 44-63.
Contemporary scientific theories assume a primarily micro-deterministic view of nature. This paper explores the question of whether micro-determinism is incompatible with the alleged emergence of properties and laws that some biologists and philosophers assert occurs in various biological systems. I argue that a preferable unified treatment of these emergence claims takes properties, rather than laws, to be the units of emergence. Four distinct conceptions of emergence are explored and three shown to be compatible with micro-determinism. The remaining concept of emergence, direct macro-determination, does not, I argue, meet the general requirement that an adequate scientific explanation provide a coherent mechanism or effective means of determination.
☞ see Roger Sperry (Jun. 1986). Macro- versus Micro-Determinism. Philosophy of Science 53(2): 265-270.
◈ Koch, Christof and Klaus Hepp (2006). Quantum mechanics in the brain. Nature 440: 611-612. (Issue of March 30, 2006).
http://klab.caltech.edu/refweb/paper/528.pdf
◇ Korn, Robert W. (Jan. 2005). The Emergence Principle in Biological Hierarchies. Biology and Philosophy 20(1) : 137-151.
Accepted: 25 March 2004
Abstract Emergent properties have been described by Mill, Lewes, Broad, Morgan and others, as novel, nonadditive, nonpredictable and nondeducible within a hierarchical context. I have developed a more definitive concept of a hierarchy that can be used to inspect the phenomenon of emergence in a new and detailed manner. A hierarchy is held together by descending constraints and new features can arise when an upper level entity restrains its components in new combinations that are not expected when viewing these components alone. Examples of emergent features are (i) matching anticodons and amino acids by aminoacetyl-tRNA synthetase enzymes appearing early among the first forms of life, (ii) negative feedback in end-product inhibition first occurring in microbes, (iii) memory in animals and (iv) apical cells in plants. Until recently, life was considered only in terms of physics and chemistry, but now it is known to have a third aspect of information that along with the descendant constraints in its hierarchical organization makes emergentism possible within a reductionist’s framework.
Keywords emergence - emergentism - hierarchy - life
◈ Krapivsky, P.L., S. Redner and F. Leyvraz (Nov. 2000). Connectivity of Growing Random Networks. Physical Review Letters 85: 4629–4632.
Received 8 May 2000
A solution for the time- and age-dependent connectivity distribution of a growing random network is presented. The network is built by adding sites that link to earlier sites with a probability Ak which depends on the number of preexisting links k to that site. For homogeneous connection kernels, Ak∼kγ, different behaviors arise for γ<1, γ>1, and γ = 1. For γ<1, the number of sites with k links, Nk, varies as a stretched exponential. For γ>1, a single site connects to nearly all other sites. In the borderline case Ak∼k, the power law Nk∼k-ν is found, where the exponent ν can be tuned to any value in the range 2<ν<∞.
▣ Kripke, Saul (1971). Identity and necessity. In: M.K. Munitz (ed.) Identity and Individuation. New York: University Press, pp. 135-164.
◈ Kronz, Frederick M., Justin T. Tiehen (June 2002). Emergence and quantum mechanics. Philosophy of Science 69(2): 324-347.
◈ Kubík, Aleš (Winter, 2003). Toward a formalization of emergence. Artificial Life 9(1): 41-65.
Abstract: Emergence is a concept widely used in the sciences, the arts, and engineering. Some effort has been made to formalize it, but it is used in various contexts with different meanings, and a unified theory of emergence is still distant. The ultimate goal of a theory of emergence should include using emergence to model, design, or predict the behavior of multiagent systems. The author proposes a formal definition of a basic type of emergence using a language-theoretic and grammar systems approach. It is shown which types of phenomena can be modeled in this sense and what the consequences are for other more complex phenomena.
◈ Kuczynski, John-Michael (Dec. 2006). Two Concepts of "Form" and the So-Called Computational Theory of Mind. Philosophical Psychology 19(6): 795-821.
Abstract: According to the computational theory of mind (CTM), to think is to compute. But what is meant by the word 'compute'? The generally given answer is this: Every case of computing is a case of manipulating symbols, but not vice versa - a manipulation of symbols must be driven exclusively by the formal properties of those symbols if it is qualify as a computation. In this paper, I will present the following argument. Words like 'form' and 'formal' are ambiguous, as they can refer to form in either the syntactic or the morphological sense. CTM fails on each disambiguation, and the arguments for CTM immediately cease to be compelling once we register that ambiguity. The terms 'mechanical' and 'automatic' are comparably ambiguous. Once these ambiguities are exposed, it turns out that there is no possibility of mechanizing thought, even if we confine ourselves to domains (such as first-order sentential logic) where all problems can be settled through decision-procedures. The impossibility of mechanizing thought thus has nothing to do with recherché mathematical theorems, such as those proven by Gödel and Rosser. A related point is that CTM involves, and is guilty of reinforcing, a misunderstanding of the concept of an algorithm.
Keywords: Computational Theory Of Mind; Formal Operation; Jerry Fodor; Syntax; Token-Semantics
◈ Lau, Hakwan C., Robert D. Rogers and Richard E. Passingham (July 5, 2006). On Measuring the Perceived Onsets of Spontaneous Actions. The Journal of Neuroscience 26(27): 7265-7271.
Received July 25, 2005; revised April 30, 2006; accepted May 23, 2006.
Abstract: We investigated the neural mechanisms underlying the timing procedure that was devised by Libet et al. (1983) to measure the onset of conscious motor intentions in spontaneous actions. We previously showed that, when participants were required to estimate the onset of their intentions using this procedure, the activity in the presupplementary motor area (pre-SMA) was enhanced. Here, we show that when participants were required to estimate the onset of their motor executions (instead of their intentions), the activity in the cingulate motor area was enhanced. Across participants, the degree of this neural enhancement was correlated with the degree of perceptual bias: the higher the degree of enhancement, the earlier the perception. Analysis of data from a previous experiment suggests that the same principle holds true for the relationship between the perceived onset of intentions and the activity in the pre-SMA. We therefore argue that the timing method of Libet et al. (1983) is problematic, because the measuring process affects the neural representations of action and thus also the perceived onsets that the method is designed to measure.
Key words: attention; motor intention; motor; movement; motion; motor activity; fMRI; motor control
◈ Lau, Hakwan C., Robert D. Rogers and Richard E. Passingham (2007). Manipulating the experienced onset of intention after action execution. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 19(1): 81-90.
Abstract: Using transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS), we have tested the time needed for the perceived onset of spontaneous motor intention to be fully determined. We found that TMS applied over the presupplementary motor area after the execution of a simple spontaneous action shifted the perceived onset of the motor intention backward in time, and shifted the perceived time of action execution forward in time. The size of the effect was similar regardless of whether TMS was applied immediately after the action or 200 msec after. The results of three control studies suggest that this effect is time-limited, specific to modality, and also specific to the anatomical site of stimulation. We conclude that the perceived onset of intention depends, at least in part, on neural activity that takes place after the execution of action. A model, which is based on the mechanism of cue integration under the presence of noise, is offered to explain the results. The implications for the conscious control of spontaneous actions are discussed.
◈ Lau, Hakwan C., Robert D. Rogers, Patrick Haggard and Richard E. Passingham (Feb. 20, 2004). Attention to intention. Science 303(5661): 1208-1210.
Abstract: Intention is central to the concept of voluntary action. Using functional magnetic resonance imaging, we compared conditions in which participants made self-paced actions and attended either to their intention to move or to the actual movement. When they attended to their intention rather than their movement, there was an enhancement of activity in the pre-supplementary motor area (pre-SMA). We also found activations in the right dorsal prefrontal cortexand left intraparietal cortex. Prefrontal activity, but not parietal activity, was more strongly coupled with activity in the pre-SMA. We conclude that activity in the pre-SMA reflects the representation of intention.
◆ Laureys, Steven (ed.) (Aug. 2005). The Boundaries of Consciousness: Neurobiology and Neuropathology (Progress in Brain Research, Volume 150). Elsevier Science.
▣ Lee, David H., Kay Severin, Yohei Yokobayashi and M. Reza Ghadiri (Dec. 1997). Emergence of symbiosis in peptide self-replication through a hypercyclic network. Nature 390(6660): 591-594 (Issue of Dec. 11, 1997).
Received 20 June 1997; Accepted 20 October 1997
Symbiosis is an association between different organisms that leads to a reciprocal enhancement of their ability to survive. Similar mutually beneficial relationships can operate at the molecular level in the form of a hypercycle, a collective of two or more self-replicating species interlinked through a cyclic catalytic network1, 2, 3, 4, 5. The superposition of cross-catalysis onto autocatalytic replication integrates the members of the hypercycle into a single system that reproduces through a second-order (or higher) form of nonlinear autocatalysis. The hypercycle population as a whole is therefore able to compete more efficiently for existing resources than any one member on its own. In addition, the effects of beneficial mutations of any one member are spread over the entire population. The formation of hypercycles has been suggested as an important step in the transition from inanimate to living chemistry6 , and a large number of hypercycles are expected to be embedded within the complex networks of living systems7. But only one naturally occurring hypercycle has been well documented8, while two autocatalytic chemical systems may contain vestiges of hypercyclic organization9,10. Here we report a chemical system that constitutes a clear example of a minimal hypercyclic network, in which two otherwise competitive self-replicating peptides symbiotically catalyse each others' production.
■ Le Poidevin, Robin (2005). Missing Elements and Missing Premises: A Combinatorial Argument for the Ontological Reduction of Chemistry. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56(1): 117–134. (doi:10.1093/phisci/axi106)
Abstract: Does chemistry reduce to physics? If this means ‘Can we derive the laws of chemistry from the laws of physics?’, recent discussions suggest that the answer is ‘no’. But supposing that kind of reduction—‘epistemological reduction’—to be impossible, the thesis of ontological reduction may still be true: that chemical properties are determined by more fundamental properties. However, even this thesis is threatened by some objections to the physicalist programme in the philosophy of mind, objections that generalize to the chemical case. Two objections are discussed: that physicalism is vacuous, and that nothing grounds the asymmetry of dependence which reductionism requires. Although it might seem rather surprising that the philosophy of chemistry is affected by shock waves from debates in the philosophy of mind, these objections show that there is an argumentative gap between, on the one hand, the theoretical connection linking chemical properties with properties at the sub-atomic level, and, on the other, the philosophical thesis of ontological reduction. The aim of this paper is to identify the missing premises (among them a theory of physical possibility) that would bridge this gap.
▣ Lewes, G.H. (1875). Problems of Life and Mind. Vol. 2. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Turbner, & Co.
◈ Libet, Benjamin, Elwood W. Wright, Bertram Feinstein, Jr and Dennis K. Pearl (Mar. 1979). Subjective referral of the timing for a conscious sensory experience: A functional role for the somatosensory specific projection system in man. Brain 102: 193-224.
◈ Libet, Benjamin, Curtis A. Gleason, Elwood W. Wright and Dennis K. Pearl (Sep. 1983). Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential): The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain 106(3): 623-642.
Received July 20, 1982. Revised December 14, 1982.
Abstract: The recordable cerebral activity (readiness-potential, RP) that precedes a freely voluntary, fully endogenous motor act was directly compared with the reportable time (W) for appearance of the subjective experience of ‘wanting’ or intending to act. The onset of cerebral activity clearly preceded by at least several hundred milliseconds the reported time of conscious intention to act. This relationship held even for those series (with ‘type II’ RPs) in which subjects reported that all of the 40 self-initiated movements in the series appeared ‘spontaneously’ and capriciously.
Data were obtained in at least 6 different experimental sessions with each of 5 subjects. In series with type II RPs, onset of the main negative shift in each RP preceded the corresponding mean W value by an average of about 350 ms, and by a minimum of about 150 ms. In series with type I RPs, in which an experience of preplanning occurred in some of the 40 self-initiated acts, onset of RP preceded W by an average of about 800 ms (or by 500 ms, taking onset of RP at 90 per cent of its area).
Reports of W time depended upon the subject's recall of the spatial ‘clock-position’ of a revolving spot at the time of his initial awareness of wanting or intending to move. Two different modes of recall produced similar values. Subjects distinguished awareness of wanting to move (W) from awareness of actually moving (M). W times were consistently and substantially negative to, in advance of, mean times reported for M and also those for S, the sensation elicited by a task-related skin stimulus delivered at irregular times that were unknown to the subject.
It is concluded that cerebral initiation of a spontaneous, freely voluntary act can begin unconsciously, that is, before there is any (at least recallable) subjective awareness that a ‘decision’ to act has already been initiated cerebrally. This introduces certain constraints on the potentiality for conscious initiation and control of voluntary acts.
◈ Libet, Benjamin, Dennis K. Pearl, David E. Morledge, Curtis A. Gleason, Yoshio Hosobuchi and Nicholas M. Barbaro (Aug. 1991). Control of the transition from sensory detection to sensory awareness in man by the duration of a thalamic stimulus: The cerebral ‘time-on’ factor. Brain 114(4): 1731-1757.
Received June 19, 1990. Revised October 30, 1990. Accepted December 6, 1990.
Summary: A ‘time-on’ theory to explain the cerebral distinction between conscious and unconscious mental functions proposes that a substantial minimum duration (‘time-on’) of appropriate neuronal activations up to about 0.5 s is required to elicit conscious sensory experience, but that durations distinctly below that minimum can mediate sensory detection without awareness. A direct experimental test of this proposal is reported here.
Stimuli (72 pulses/s) above and below such minimum train durations (0–750 ms) were delivered to the ventrobasal thalamus via electrodes chronically implanted for the therapeutic control of intractable pain. Detection was measured by the subject's forced choice as to stimulus delivery in one of two intervals, regardless of any presence or absence of sensory awareness. Subjects also indicated their awareness level of any stimulus-induced sensation in each and every trial. The results show (1) that detection (correct > 50%) occurred even with stimulus durations too brief to elicit awareness, and (2) that to move from mere detection to even an uncertain and often questionable sensory awareness required a significantly larger additional duration of pulses. Thus simply increasing duration (‘time-on’) of the same repetitive inputs to cerebral cortex can convert an unconscious cognitive mental function (detection without awareness) to a conscious one (detection with awareness).
◈ Linde, Andrei (Nov. 8, 2002). Inflation, quantum cosmology and the anthropic principle. Published in Johh D. Barrow, Paul C.W. Davies and Charles L. Harper, Jr. eds. (June, 2004). Science and Ultimate Reality: Quantum Theory, Cosmology and Complexity (honoring John Wheeler's 90th birthday). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (pp. 426-458).
◈ Litt, Abninder, Chris Eliasmith, Frederick W. Kroon, Steven Weinstein and Paul Thagard (2006). Is the brain a quantum computer, Cognitive Science 30(3): 593-603.
http://watarts.uwaterloo.ca/~celiasmi/Papers/litt%20et%20al.2006.quantum%20brain.cogsci.pdf
☞ see A reply from Stuart R. Hameroff, a Pioneer and Researcher of Quantum Consciousness whom Abninder Litt et al. criticize.
◈ Lloyd, Seth (2000). Ultimate physical limits to computation. Nature 406: 1047-1054 (Issue of Aug. 31, 2000).
◈ Lloyd, Seth (June 10, 2002). Computational capacity of the universe. Physical Review Letters 88(23): 237901-4.
▣ Logan, Robert K. (2006) The extended mind model of the origin of language and culture. In: Nathalie, Gontier, Jean Paul van Bendegem and Diederik Aerts (eds.) (2006). Evolutionary epistemology, language and culture: A non-adaptationist, systems theoretical approach. Dordrecht: Springer.
▣ Logan, Robert K. (Sep. 2007). The Extended Mind: The Emergence of Language, the Human Mind, and Culture (Toronto Studies in Semiotics and Communication). Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
The ability to communicate through language is such a fundamental part of human existence that we often take it for granted, rarely considering how sophisticated the process is by which we understand and make ourselves understood. In The Extended Mind, acclaimed author Robert K. Logan examines the origin, emergence, and co-evolution of language, the human mind, and culture.
Building on his previous study, The Sixth Language (2000) and making use of emergence theory, Logan seeks to explain how language emerged to deal with the complexity of hominid existence brought about by tool-making, control of fire, social intelligence, coordinated hunting and gathering, and mimetic communication. The resulting emergence of language, he argues, signifies a fundamental change in the functioning of the human mind – a shift from percept-based thought to concept-based thought.
From the perspective of the Extended Mind model, Logan provides an alternative to and critique of Noam Chomsky’s approach to the origin of language. He argues that language can be treated as an organism that evolved to be easily acquired, obviating the need for the hard-wiring of Chomsky’s Language Acquisition Device. In addition Logan shows how, according to this model, culture itself can be treated as an organism that has evolved to be easily attained, revealing the universality of human culture as well as providing an insight as to how altruism might have originated. Bringing timely insights to a fascinating field of inquiry, The Extended Mind will be sure to find a wide readership.
Robert K. Logan is a professor emeritus in the Department of Physics at the University of Toronto.
http://www.utppublishing.com/pubstore/merchant.ihtml?pid=8841&step=4
■ Lombardi, Olimpia and Martín Labarca (Jan. 2005). The Ontological Autonomy of The Chemical World. Foundations of Chemistry 7(2): 125-148.
Abstract: In the problem of the relationship between chemistry and physics, many authors take for granted the ontological reduction of the chemical world to the world of physics. The autonomy of chemistry is usually defended on the basis of the failure of epistemological reduction: not all chemical concepts and laws can be derived from the theoretical framework of physics. The main aim of this paper is to argue that this line of argumentation is not strong enough for eliminate the idea of a hierarchical dependence of chemistry with respect to physics. The rejection of the secondary position of chemistry and the defense of the legitimacy of the philosophy of chemistry require a radically different philosophical perspective that denies not only epistemological reduction but also ontological reduction. Only on the basis of a philosophically grounded ontological pluralism it is possible to accept the ontological autonomy of the chemical world and, with this, to reverse the traditional idea of the ‘superiority’ of physics in the context of natural sciences.
◇ Looijen, Rick C. (Richard Christiaan) (2000/2007). Holism and Reductionism in Biology and Ecology: The Mutual Dependence of Higher and Lower Level Research Programmes. (Episteme Series Vol. 23). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers/Berlin: Springer.
About this book
Holism and reductionism are traditionally seen as incompatible views or approaches to nature. Here Looijen argues that they should rather be seen as mutually dependent and hence co-operating research programmes. He sheds some interesting new light on the emergence thesis, its relation to the reduction thesis, and on the role and status of functional explanations in biology. He discusses several examples of reduction in both biology and ecology, showing the mutual dependence of holistic and reductionist research programmes. Ecologists are offered separate chapters, clarifying some major, yet highly and controversial ecological concepts, such as `community', `habitat', and `niche'. The book is the first in-depth study of the philosophy of ecology.
Table of contents
▣ Looren de Jong, Huib (Dec. 2002). Levels of explanation in biological psychology. Philosophical Psychology. 15(4): 441-462.
Abstract: Until recently, the notions of function and multiple realization were supposed to save the autonomy of psychological explanations. Furthermore, the concept of supervenience presumably allows both dependence of mind on brain and non-reducibility of mind to brain, reconciling materialism with an independent explanatory role for mental and functional concepts and explanations. Eliminativism is often seen as the main or only alternative to such autonomy. It gladly accepts abandoning or thoroughly reconstructing the psychological level, and considers reduction if successful as equivalent with elimination. In comparison with the philosophy of mind, the philosophy of biology has developed more subtle and complex ideas about functions, laws, and reductive explanation than the stark dichotomy of autonomy or elimination. It has been argued that biology is a patchwork of local laws, each with different explanatory interests and more or less limited scope. This points to a pluralistic, domain-specific and multi-level view of explanations in biology. Explanatory pluralism has been proposed as an alternative to eliminativism on the one hand and methodological dualism on the other hand. It holds that theories at different levels of description, like psychology and neuroscience, can co-evolve, and mutually influence each other, without the higher-level theory being replaced by, or reduced to, the lower-level one. Such ideas seem to tally with the pluralistic character of biological explanation. In biological psychology, explanatory pluralism would lead us to expect many local and non-reductive interactions between biological, neurophysiological, psychological and evolutionary explanations of mind and behavior. This idea is illustrated by an example from behavioral genetics, where genetics, physiology and psychology constitute distinct but interrelated levels of explanation. Accounting for such a complex patchwork of related explanations seems to require a more sophisticated and precise way of looking at levels than the existing ideas on (reductive and non-reductive) explanation in the philosophy of mind.
▣ Looren de Jong, Huib (June 1, 2003). Causal and Functional Explanations. Theory and Psychology 13(3): 291 - 317.
Abstract: Functional explanation, for long the mainstay of psychology's autonomy, has recently come under attack. It is sometimes argued that higher-level generalizations are causally impotent, and do not really explain anything. Presumably only the reduction of higher-level patterns to underlying causal physical properties, and the specifying of lower-level, local causal mechanisms, provides genuine explanations. Two lines of argument are critically discussed: causal exclusion and multiple realization. These bear upon the credibility of functional explanation, and upon the presumed explanatory superiority of causal mechanisms over functional higher-level generalizations. It is argued that the causal exclusion argument conflates metaphysics with explanation, and that, rather than pointing towards reductionism, multiple realization indicates the indispensability of higher (functional) generalizations, alongside lower (causal) explanations; the choice for higher or lower level depends on context and explanatory interest. The notion of screening-off suggests a criterion for the legitimacy of higher-level characterizations. A brief example from the history of genetics is discussed to illustrate these ideas. This leads to a plea for pluralism in explanation.
Key Words: causal explanation • cognitive science • functional explanation • genetics • multiple realization • reduction • screening-off • supervenience
◆ Lovejoy, A.O. (1927). The meanings of "emergence" and its modes. In: E. S. Brightman (ed.) Proceedings of the Sixth International Congress of Philosophy. Longmans, Green, and Co.
◈ Lowe, E. Jonathan (Oct. 2000). Causal closure principles and emergentism. Philosophy 75(4): 571-585.
Published online by Cambridge University Press 11 Dec. 2000
Causal closure arguments against interactionist dualism are currently popular amongst physicalists. Such an argument appeals to some principles of the causal closure of the physical, together with certain other premises, to conclude that at least some mental events are identical with physical events. However, it is crucial to the success of any such argument that the physical causal closure principle to which it appeals is neither too strong nor too weak by certain standards. In this paper, it is argued that various forms of naturalistic dualism, of an emergentist character, are consistent with the strongest physical causal closure principles that can plausibly be advocated.
◈ Lowe, E. Jonathan (Dec. 2006). Non-Cartesian substance dualism and the problem of mental causation. Erkenntnis 65(1): 5-23.
Published online: 17 October 2006
Abstract: Non-Cartesian substance dualism (NCSD) maintains that persons or selves are distinct from their organic physical bodies and any parts of those bodies. It regards persons as ‘substances’ in their own right, but does not maintain that persons are necessarily separable from their bodies, in the sense of being capable of disembodied existence. In this paper, it is urged that NCSD is better equipped than either Cartesian dualism or standard forms of physicalism to explain the possibility of mental causation. A model of mental causation adopting the NCSD perspective is proposed which, it is argued, is consistent with all that is currently known about the operations of the human central nervous system, including the brain. Physicalism, by contrast, seems ill-equipped to explain the distinctively intentional or teleological character of mental causation, because it effectively reduces all such causation to ‘blind’ physical causation at a neurological level.
◆ Lowry, Ann (Apr. 1974). A Note on Emergence. Mind, New Series, Vol. 83, No. 330: 276-277.
◇ Lucas, John R. (1995). The Unity of Science without Reductionism. Acta Analytica 10(15):
Abstract: The Unity of Science is often thought to be reductionist, but this is because we fail to distinguish questions from answers. The questions asked by different sciences are different - the biologist is interested in different topics from the physicist, and seeks different explanations - but the answers are not peculiar to each particular science, and can range over the whole of scientific knowledge. The biologist is interested in organisms - concept unknown to physics - but explains physiological processes in terms of chemistry, not a mysterious vital force. The replacement of Laplacian determinism by quantum mechanics further erodes the tendency towards reductionism. The answers given in different explanations are not subsumed under one complete theory; and quantum mechanics does not have a concept of haecceitas, "this-i-ness" which would make its entities the fundamental constituents of everything.
◈ Luisi, Pier Luigi (Oct. 2004). Emergence in Chemistry: Chemistry as the Embodiment of Emergence. Foundations of Chemistry 4(3): 183-200.
◈ Luisi, Pier Luigi (2006). The emergence of life: From chemical origins to synthetic biology. Cambridge University Press.
◇ Lyon, Caroline, Chrystopher L. Nehaniv and Angelo Cangelosi (eds.) (Feb. 2007). Emergence of Communication and Language. Springer.
Old questions on the origins of language and communication are illuminated here in new, state-of-the-art research.
This volume brings together studies from diverse disciplines, showing how they can inform and stimulate each other. It includes work in linguistics, psychology, neuroscience, anthropology and computer science. New empirical work is reported on both human and animal communication, using some novel techniques that have only recently become viable.
A principal theme is the importance of studies involving artificial agents, their contribution to the body of knowledge on the emergence of communication and language, and the role of simulations in exploring some of the most significant issues. A number of different synthetic systems are described, demonstrating how communication can emerge in natural and artificial organisms. Theories on the origins of language are supported by computational and robotic experiments.
Worldwide contributors to this volume include some of the most influential figures in the field, delivering essential reading for researchers and graduates in the area, as well as providing fascinating insights for a wider readership.
Caroline Lyon is a Senior Lecturer in Computer Science at the University of Hertfordshire. Her research and publications include work on the evolution of language, speech recognition, applications of neural networks and textual analysis. Chrystopher L. Nehaniv is Research Professor of Mathematical and Evolutionary Computer Science at the University of Hertfordshire and Director of the U.K. Engineering and Physical Sciences Research Council Network on Evolvability in Biological and Software Systems. Angelo Cangelosi is Reader in Artificial Intelligence and Cognition at the University of Plymouth. He is the editor of Simulating the Evolution of Language (Springer, 2002).
TABLE OF CONTENTS
List of Contributors ix
INTRODUCTION
1. Current Work and Open Problems: A Road-Map for Research into the Emergence of Communication and Language
Chrystopher L. Nehaniv, Caroline Lyon, and Angelo Cangelosi. . . . . 1
PART I EMPIRICAL INVESTIGATIONS ON HUMAN LANGUAGE
2. Evolving Meaning: The Roles of Kin Selection, Allomothering and Paternal Care in Language Evolution
W. Tecumseh Fitch. . . . . 29
3. ‘Needs only’ Analysis in Linguistic Ontogeny and Phylogeny
Alison Wray. . . . . 53
4. Clues from Information Theory Indicating a Phased Emergence of Grammar
Caroline Lyon, Chrystopher L. Nehaniv, and Bob Dickerson. . . . . 71
5. Emergence of a Communication System: International Sign
Rachel Rosenstock. . . . . 87
6. Distributed Language: Biomechanics, Functions, and the Origins of Talk
Stephen J. Cowley. . . . . 105
PART II SYNTHESIS OF COMMUNICATION AND LANGUAGE IN ARTIFICIAL SYSTEMS
7. The Recruitment Theory of Language Origins
Luc Steels. . . . . 129
8. In silico Evolutionary Developmental Neurobiology and the Origin of Natural Language
Eörs Szathmáry, Zoltán Szatmáry, Péter Ittzés, Gergö Orban, István Zachár, Ferenc Huszár, Anna Fedor, Máté Varga, Szabolcs Számadó. . . . . 151
9. Communication in Natural and Artificial Organisms: Experiments in Evolutionary Robotics
Davide Marocco and Stefano Nolfi. . . . . 189
10. From Vocal Replication to Shared Combinatorial Speech Codes: A Small Step for Evolution, A Big Step for Language
Pierre-Yves Oudeyer. . . . . 207
11. Learning and Transition of Symbols: Towards a Dynamical Model of a Symbolic Individual
Takashi Hashimoto and Akira Masumi . . . . . 223
12. Language Change among ‘Memoryless Learners’ Simulated in Language Dynamics Equations
Makoto Nakamura, Takashi Hashimoto, and Satoshi Tojo. . . . . 237
13. The Evolution of Meaning-Space Structure through Iterated Learning
Simon Kirby. . . . . 253
14. The Emergence of Language: How to Simulate It
Domenico Parisi and Marco Mirolli. . . . . 269
15. Lexical Acquisition with and without Metacommunication
Jonathan Ginzburg and Zoran Macura. . . . . 287
16. Agent Based Modelling of Communication Costs: Why Information Can Be Free
Ivana Čače and Joanna J. Bryson. . . . . 305
17. Language Change and the Inference of Meaning
Andrew D. M. Smith. . . . . 323
18. Language, Perceptual Categories and their Interaction: Insights from Computational Modelling
Tony Belpaeme and Joris Bleys. . . . . 339
PART III INSIGHTS FROM ANIMAL COMMUNICATION
19. Emergence of Linguistic Communication: Studies on Grey Parrots
Irene M. Pepperberg. . . . . 355
20. A Possible Role for Selective Masking in the Evolution of Complex, Learned Communication Systems
Graham R. S. Ritchie and Simon Kirby. . . . . 387
21. The Natural History of Human Language: Bridging the Gaps without Magic
Bjorn Merker and Kazuo Okanoya. . . . . 403
22. Neural Substrates for String-Context Mutual Segmentation: A Path to Human Language
Kazuo Okanoya and Bjorn Merker. . . . . 421
Index 435
Sample pages: download 1846284910-c2.pdf (pdf, 221 Kb)
http://www.springer.com/east/home/generic/search/results?SGWID=5-40109-22-172423533-0
◈ Lyons, Jack C. (Dec. 2006). In Defense of Epiphenomenalism. Philosophical Psychology 19(6): 767-794.
Abstract: Recent worries about possible epiphenomenalist consequences of nonreductive physicalism are misplaced, not, as many have argued, because nonreductive physicalism does not imply epiphenomenalism but because the epiphenomenalist implication is actually a virtue of the theory, rather than a vice. It is only by showing how certain kinds of mental properties are causally impotent that cognitive scientific explanations of mentality as we know them are possible.
Keywords: Functionalism; Epiphenomenalism; Nonreductive Physicalism; Type Materialism; Mental Causation; Reduction
■ Macdonald, Cynthia (Apr. 2007). Critical notices: PHYSICALISM, OR SOMETHING NEAR ENOUGH. Philosophical Books 48 (2): 155–161. (doi:10.1111/j.1468-0149.2007.00439.x)
◇ Macdonald, Cynthia and Graham Macdonald (Nov. 2007). The Metaphysics of Mental Causation. The Journal of Philosophy 103(11):
A Draft of this paper:
www.phil.canterbury.ac.nz/personal_pages/
First two paragraphs of the Draft:
◈ Macgregor, R.J. (Sep. 2006). Quantum mechanics and brain uncertainty. Journal of integrative neuroscience 5(3): 373-80.
◆ Mackenzie, W.L. (1926). The notion of emergence. Aristotelian Society Supplement 6: 56-68.
◈ Maclennan, B. J. (2001). The emergence of communication through synthetic evolution. Published pp. 65-90 in: M. Patel, V. Honavar & K. Balakrishnan (eds.) Advances in the Evolutionary Synthesis of Intelligent Agents. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
◈ MacWhinney, Brian (Dec. 2006). Emergentism—Use Often and With Care. Applied Linguistics 27(4): 729-740.
☞ see also Ke Jinyun and John H. Holland's paper that deals with the language origin from an emergentist perspective.
◇ MacWhinney, Brian (ed.) (Feb. 1999). The Emergence of Language (Carnegie Mellon Symposia Cognition Series). Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
About the book
For nearly four centuries, our understanding of human development has been controlled by the debate between nativism and empiricism. Nowhere has the contrast between these apparent alternatives been sharper than in the study of language acquisition. However, as more is learned about the details of language learning, it is found that neither nativism nor empiricism provides guidance about the ways in which complexity arises from the interaction of simpler developmental forces. For example, the child's first guesses about word meanings arise from the interplay between parental guidance, the child's perceptual preferences, and neuronal support for information storage and retrieval. As soon as the shape of the child's lexicon emerges from these more basic forces, an exploration of "emergentism" as a new alternative to nativism and empiricism is ready to begin.
This book presents a series of emergentist accounts of language acquisition. Each case shows how a few simple, basic processes give rise to new levels of language complexity. The aspects of language examined here include auditory representations, phonological and articulatory processes, lexical semantics, ambiguity processing, grammaticality judgment, and sentence comprehension. The approaches that are invoked to account formally for emergent patterns include neural network theory, dynamic systems, linguistic functionalism, construction grammar, optimality theory, and statistically-driven learning. The excitement of this work lies both in the discovery of new emergent patterns and in the integration of theoretical frameworks that can formalize the theory of emergentism.
Table of contents
Preface
J.L. Elman, The Emergence of Language: A Conspiracy Theory.
E. Bates, J.C. Goodman, On the Emergence of Grammar From the Lexicon.
T. Givón, Generativity and Variation: The Notion 'Rule of Grammar' Revisited.
J. Allen, M.S. Seidenberg, The Emergence of Grammaticality in Connectionist Networks.
R. Miikkulainen, M.R. Mayberry, III, Disambiguation and Grammar as Emergent Soft Constraints.
M.C. MacDonald, Distributional Information in Language Comprehension, Production, and Acquisition: Three Puzzles and a Moral.
A.E. Goldberg, The Emergence of the Semantics of Argument Structure Constructions.
B. MacWhinney, The Emergence of Language From Embodiment.
C.E. Snow, Social Perspectives on the Emergence of Language.
L.B. Smith, Children's Noun Learning: How General Learning Processes Make Specialized Learning Mechanisms.
R.M. Golinkoff, K. Hirsh-Pasek, G. Hollich, Emergent Cues for Early Word Learning.
W.E. Merriman, Competition, Attention, and Young Children's Lexical Processing.
R.N. Aslin, J.R. Saffran, E.L. Newport, Statistical Learning in Linguistic and Nonlinguistic Domains.
D.C. Plaut, C.T. Kello, The Emergence of Phonology From the Interplay of Speech Comprehension and Production: A Distributed Connectionist Approach.
J.P. Stemberger, B.H. Bernhardt, The Emergence of Faithfulness.
P. Gupta, G.S. Dell, The Emergence of Language From Serial Order and Procedural Memory.
◈ Mainzer, Klaus (2003). Thinking in Complexity: The Computational Dynamics of Matter, Mind, and Mankind. (4th edition). Berlin/Heidelberg/New York: Springer.
◈ Mainzer, Klaus (2005). Symmetry and Complexity: The Spirit and Beauty of Nonlinear Science. Singapore: World Scientific Publishing Co.
◈ Mainzer, Klaus (in press). The Emergence of Mind and Brain. An Evolutionary, Computational, and Philosophical Approach. In Bikas K. Chakrabarti and Rahul Banerjee eds. Models of Brain and Mind: Physical, Computational, and Psychological Approaches. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Abstract: Modern philosophy of mind cannot be understood without recent developments in computer science, artificial intelligence (AI), robotics, neuroscience, biology, linguistics, and psychology. Classical philosophy of formal languages as well as symbolic AI assume that all kinds of knowledge must explicitly be represented by formal or programming languages. This assumption is limited by recent insights into the biology of evolution and developmental psychology of the human organism. Most of our knowledge is implicit and unconscious. It is not formally represented, but embodied knowledge, which is learnt by doing and understood by bodily interacting with changing environments. That is true not only of low level skills, but even for high level domains of categorization, language and abstract thinking. The embodied mind is considered an emergent capacity of the brain as a self-organizing complex system. Actually, self-organization has been a successful strategy of evolution to handle the increasing complexity of the world. Genetic programs are not sufficient and cannot prepare for all kinds of complex situations in the future. Self-organization and emergence are fundamental concepts in the theory of complex dynamical systems. They are also applied in organic computing as a recent research field of computer science. Therefore, cognitive science, AI, and robotics try to model the embodied mind in an artificial evolution. The paper analyses these approaches in the interdisciplinary framework of complex dynamical systems and discusses their philosophical impact.
◇ Malaterre, Christophe (Mar. 2007). Organicism and Reductionism in Cancer Research: Towards a Systemic Approach. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 21(1): 57-73. (DOI: 10.1080/02698590701305792)
Abstract: In recent cancer research, strong and apparently conflicting epistemological stances have been advocated by different research teams in a mist of an ever-growing body of knowledge ignited by ever-more perplexing and non-conclusive experimental facts: in the past few years, an 'organicist' approach investigating cancer development at the tissue level has challenged the established and so-called 'reductionist' approach focusing on disentangling the genetic and molecular circuitry of carcinogenesis. This article reviews the ways in which 'organicism' and 'reductionism' are used and opposed in this context, with an aim at clarifying the debate. Methodological, epistemological and ontological implications of both approaches are discussed. We argue that the 'organicist/reductionist' opposition in the present case of carcinogenesis is more a matter of diverging heuristics than a claim about theoretical or ontological (ir)reducibility. As a matter of fact, except for the downward causation claim, which we question, we argue that the organicist arguments are compatible with the reductionist approach. Moreover, we speculate that both approaches, which currently focus on specific entities i.e., genes versus tissues, will need to shift their conceptual frameworks to studying complex arrays of relationships potentially ranging over several levels of entities, as is the case with 'systems biology'.
◇ Marcum, James A. (Mar. 2005). Metaphysical presuppositions and scientific practices: Reductionism and organicism in cancer research. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 19(1): 31-45. (DOI: 10.1080/02698590500051076)
Abstract: Metaphysical presuppositions are important for guiding scientific practices and research. The success of twentieth-century biology, for instance, is largely attributable to presupposing that complex biological processes are reducible to elementary components. However, some biologists have challenged the sufficiency of reductionism for investigating complex biological phenomena and have proposed alternative presuppositions like organicism. In this article, contemporary cancer research is used as a case study to explore the importance of metaphysical presuppositions for guiding research. The predominant paradigm directing cancer research is the somatic mutation theory, in which mutated genes are presumed to be ultimately responsible for explaining carcinogenesis. This reductionistic approach to cancer has been criticised recently, and an organistic approach has been proposed. The article concludes with a discussion of the reciprocal interaction of metaphysical presuppositions and scientific practices for investigating cancer's complex nature.
◈ Marcus, Eric (2005). Mental causation in a physical world. Synthese 122(1): 27-50.
Abstract: It is generally accepted that the most serious threat to the possibility of mental causation is posed by the causal self-sufficiency of physical causal processes. I argue, however, that this feature of the world, which I articulate in principle I call Completeness, in fact poses no genuine threat to mental causation. Some find Completeness threatening to mental causation because they confuse it with a stronger principle, which I call Closure. Others do not simply conflate Completeness and Closure, but hold that Completeness, together with certain plausible assumptions, entails Closure. I refute the most fully worked-out version of such an argument. Finally, some find Completeness all by itself threatening to mental causation. I argue that one will only find Completeness threatening if one operates with a philosophically distorted conception of mental causation. I thereby defend what I call naïve realism about mental causation.
http://www.auburn.edu/~marcuea/MCPWsamp.pdf
◆ Margolis, J. (1986). Emergence. Philosophical Forum 17: 271-295.
◈ Margulis, Lynn (Apr. 2001). The conscious cell. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 929(1): 55-70.
◇ Markič, Olga (2004). Causal Emergentism. Acta Analytica 19(33):
Abstract: In this paper I describe basic features of traditional (British) emergentism and Popper's emergentist theory of consciousness and compare them to the contemporary versions of emergentism present in connectionist approach in cognitive sciences. I argue that despite their similarities, the traditional form, as well as Popper's theory belong to strong causal emergentism and yield radically different ontological consequences compared to the weaker, contemporary version present in cognitive science. Strong causal emergentism denies the causal closure of the physical domain and introduces genuine new mental causal powers and genuine downward causation, while weak emergentism provides new insights in understanding the mechanisms and explanation that is compatible with physicalism.
▣ Marras, Ausonio (Apr. 1993). Supervenience and Reducibility: An Odd Couple. Philosophical Quarterly 43(171):215–222.
▣ Marras, Ausonio (Sep. 1998). Kim’s Principle of Explanatory Exclusion. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76(3):439–451.
▣ Marras, Ausonio (2000). Critical Notice of Mind in a Physical World. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30: 137–160.
◈ Marras, Ausonio (2002). Kim on reduction. Erkenntnis 57(2): 231-257.
Abstract: In Mind in a Physical World (1998), Jaegwon Kim has recently extended his ongoing critique of `non-reductive materialist' positions in philosophy of mind by arguing that Nagel's model of reduction is the wrong paradigm in terms of which to contest the issue of psychophysical reduction, and that an altogether different model of scientific reduction – a functional model of reduction – is needed. In this paper I argue, first, that Kim's conception of the Nagelian model is substantially impoverished and potentially misleading; second, that his own functional model is problematic in several respects; and, third, that the basic idea underlying his functional model can well be accommodated within a properly reinterpreted Nagelian model. I conclude with some reflections on the issue of psychophysical reduction.
▣ Marras, Ausonio (2005). Consciousness and Reduction. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56(2): 335–361.
A number of philosophers—among them Joseph Levine, David Chalmers, Frank Jackson and Jaegwon Kim—have claimed that there are conceptual grounds sufficient for ruling out the possibility of a reductive explanation of phenomenal consciousness. Their claim assumes a functional model of reduction (regarded by Kim as an alternative to the traditional Nagelian model) which requires an a priori entailment from the facts in the reduction base to the phenomena to be explained. The aim of this paper is to show that this is an unreasonable requirement—a requirement that no reductive explanation in science should be expected to satisfy. I argue that the functional model is not substantively different from the Nagelian model properly understood, and that the question whether consciousness is reductively explainable—in a sense involving property identifications or in some weaker sense compatible with Nagelian reduction—is a fundamentally empirical question, not one that can be settled on conceptual grounds alone.
◈ Marras, Ausonio (2006). Emergence and reduction: Reply to Kim. Synthese 151(3): 561-569.
Published online: 15 August 2006
Keywords: Emergence - Jaegwon Kim - Nonreductive physicalism - Reduction - Reductive explanation - Supervenience
▣ Marras, Ausonio (May 2007). Kim’s Supervenience Argument and Nonreductive Physicalism. Erkenntnis 66(3): 305-327.
Received: 19 January 2006 Accepted: 8 December 2006 Published online: 2 February 2007
Keywords: Kim - nonreductive physicalism - supervenience - mental causation
◈ Maturana, Humberto R. and Franciso J. Varela (1980). Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living. Boston: Reidel. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, volume 42. Kluwer Academic Publishers.
◆ Maturana, Humberto R. and Franciso J. Varela (1993). The Tree of Knowledge: The Biological Roots of Human Understanding. Shambhala Publications, Inc.
☞ 한국어판『앎의 나무』는 중요한 철학적/인지과학적 개념 중 몇 가지를 부적절하게 번역했음.
차후에 이 한국어판의 번역을 비판할 것임.
▣ Maynard Smith, John (2000). The concept of information in biology. Philosophy of Science 67:177–194.
◈ McClamrock, Ron (1993). Emergence unscathed: Kim on non-reducible types. The Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy.
http://www.albany.edu/~ron/papers/Kim-ejap.html
◈ McDonough, Richard (2002). Emergence and Creativity: Five Degrees of Freedom. In Terry Dartnell (ed.) Creativity, Cognition and Knowledge: An Interaction. Westport CT: Praeger, 283-320.
◈ McFadden, Johnjoe (2002). Synchronous firing and its influence on the brain's electromagnetic field: Evidence for an electromagnetic field theory of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 9(4): 23-50.
Abstract: The human brain consists of approximately 100 billion electrically active neurones that generate an endogenous electromagnetic (em) field, whose role in neuronal computing has not been fully examined. The source, magnitude and likely influence of the brain’s endogenous em field are here considered. An estimate of the strength and magnitude of the brain’s em field is gained from theoretical considerations, brain scanning and microelectrode data. An estimate of the likely influence of the brain’s em field is gained from theoretical principles and considerations of the experimental effects of external em fields on neurone firing both in vitro and in vivo. Synchronous firing of distributed neurones phase-locks induced em field fluctuations to increase their magnitude and influence. Synchronous firing has previously been demonstrated to correlate with awareness and perception, indicating that perturbations to the brain’s em field also correlate with awareness. The brain’s em field represents an integrated electromagnetic field representation of distributed neuronal information and has dynamics that closely map to those expected for a correlate of consciousness. I propose that the brain’s em information field is the physical substrate of conscious awareness — the cemi field — and make a number of predictions that follow from this proposal. Experimental evidence pertinent to these predictions is examined and shown to be entirely consistent with the cemi field theory. This theory provides solutions to many of the intractable problems of consciousness — such as the binding problem — and provides new insights into the role of consciousness, the meaning of free will and the nature of qualia. It thus places consciousness within a secure physical framework and provides a route towards constructing an artificial consciousness.
◈ McFadden, Johnjoe (2002). The conscious electromagnetic information (Cemi) field theory: The Hard Problem made easy? Journal of Consciousness Studies 9(8): 45-60.
Abstract: In the April 2002 edition of JCS I outlined the conscious electromagnetic information field (cemi field) theory, claiming that consciousness is that component of the brain’s electromagnetic field that is downloaded to motor neurons and is thereby capable of communicating its informational content to the outside world. In this paper I demonstrate that the theory is robust to criticisms. I further explore implications of the theory particularly as regards the relationship between electromagnetic fields, information, the phenomenology of consciousness and the meaning of free will. Using cemi field theory I propose a working hypothesis that shows, among other things, that awareness and information represent the same phenomenon viewed from different reference frames.
◈ McIntyre, Lee (1999). The emergence of the philosophy of chemistry. Foundations of Chemistry 1(1): 57-63.
◈ McIntyre, Lee (Apr. 2002). Supervenience and explanatory exclusion. Crítica, Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía Vol. 34, No. 100: 87–101.
http://critica.filosoficas.unam.mx/pdf/C100/C100lee.pdf
Abstract: This paper argues that there is an inconsistency between Jaegwon Kim's earlier work on supervenience and his more recent work on explanatory exclusion. In his work on supervenience Kim advocates an explanatory agnosticism that, by the time of his later work, is replaced by an endorsement of reductive explanation. My argument is that this tension between Kim's early and later work is unfortunate since explanatory exclusion is highly questionable in its own right and is not reconcilable with his earlier work on supervenience anyway.
Keywords: supervenience, explanatory exclusion, reductionism, Jaegwon Kim
◈ McIntyre, Lee (Apr, 2007). Emergence and reduction in chemistry: ontological or epistemological concepts? Synthese 155(3): 337-343.
Received: 8 May 2006 Accepted: 30 August 2006 Published online: 21 November 2006
Keywords: Philosophy of Chemistry - Emergence - Reduction - Ontology - Epistemology
◈ McLaughlin, Brian P. (1992). The Rise and Fall of British Emergentism. Published pp. 49-93 in: Beckermann, Ansgar, Hans Flohr, Jaegwon Kim (eds.) Emergence or Reduction? - Essays on the Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism. Berlin: Walter de Gruyte.
◈ McLaughlin, Brian P. (1995). Varieties of Supervenience. Published pp. 16-59 in: E. Savellos, and U. Yalcin (eds.) Supervenience: New Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
◈ McLaughlin, Brian P. (1997). Emergence and Supervenience. Intellectica 25: 25-43.
http://www.utc.fr/arco/publications/intellectica
◈ McLaughlin, Brian P. (1999). Emergence. Published pp. 267-269 in: Robert. A. Wilson, and Frank C. Keil (eds.) The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
◈ McLaughlin, Brian P. (2003). Vitalism and Emergence. Published pp. 631-39 in: T. Baldwin (ed.) The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870-1945. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
◈ McLaughlin, Brian P. (Forthcoming). A Primer on Supervenience.
◆ Meehl, Paul E. and Wilfrid Sellars (1956). The Concept of Emergence. In: Herbert Feigl and Michael Scriven (eds.) Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume I: The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis. University of Minnesota Press, pp. 239-252.
First Paragraph: Somewhat over a quarter of a century ago, Professor Stephen Pepper published a paper on "Emergence"{1} which was (and still is) symptomatic of a certain way of thinking on this topic. The paper had the virtues of brevity and clarity, and, which is more important, it went to the heart of the matter. The fact that the crucial step in its argument is a simple non sequitur by no means detracts from its diagnostic value as a document in the controversy over emergence.
http://www.ditext.com/sellars/ce.html
◈ Meijers, Anthonie W.M. (2000). Mental causation and Searle's impossible conception of unconscious intentionality. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 8(2): 155-170.
◇ Mellor, Hugh, and Tim Crane (1990). There Is No Question of Physicalism. Mind 99: 185 206.
◇ Merker, Bjorn (Feb. 2007). Consciousness without a cerebral cortex: A challenge for neuroscience and medicine. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30(1): 63-81. (doi: 10.1017/S0140525X07000891)
Published online by Cambridge University Press 01 May 2007
Abstract: A broad range of evidence regarding the functional organization of the vertebrate brain – spanning from comparative neurology to experimental psychology and neurophysiology to clinical data – is reviewed for its bearing on conceptions of the neural organization of consciousness. A novel principle relating target selection, action selection, and motivation to one another, as a means to optimize integration for action in real time, is introduced. With its help, the principal macrosystems of the vertebrate brain can be seen to form a centralized functional design in which an upper brain stem system organized for conscious function performs a penultimate step in action control. This upper brain stem system retained a key role throughout the evolutionary process by which an expanding forebrain – culminating in the cerebral cortex of mammals – came to serve as a medium for the elaboration of conscious contents. This highly conserved upper brainstem system, which extends from the roof of the midbrain to the basal diencephalon, integrates the massively parallel and distributed information capacity of the cerebral hemispheres into the limited-capacity, sequential mode of operation required for coherent behavior. It maintains special connective relations with cortical territories implicated in attentional and conscious functions, but is not rendered nonfunctional in the absence of cortical input. This helps explain the purposive, goal-directed behavior exhibited by mammals after experimental decortication, as well as the evidence that children born without a cortex are conscious. Taken together these circumstances suggest that brainstem mechanisms are integral to the constitution of the conscious state, and that an adequate account of neural mechanisms of conscious function cannot be confined to the thalamocortical complex alone.
Key Words: action selection; anencephaly; central decision making; consciousness; control architectures; hydranencephaly; macrosystems; motivation; target selection; zona incerta.
☞ see Open Peer Commentaries from many specialists in Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30(1): 81-110.
◇ Merker, Bjorn (Feb. 2007). Author's Response - Grounding consciousness: The mesodiencephalon as thalamocortical base. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30(1): 110-120. (doi: 10.1017/S0140525X07001173)
Published online by Cambridge University Press 01 May 2007
Abstract: My response addresses general commentary themes such as my neglect of the forebrain contribution to human consciousness, the bearing of blindsight on consciousness theory, the definition of wakefulness, the significance of emotion and pain perception for consciousness theory, and concerns regarding remnant cortex in children with hydranencephaly. Further specific topics, such as phenomenal and phylogenetic aspects of mesodiencephalic-thalamocortical relations, are also discussed.
◈ Merricks, Trenton (Jan. 1998). Against the doctrine of microphysical supervenience. Mind 107(425): 59-71.
◈ Metzinger, Thomas (ed.) (2000). Neural Correlates of Consciousness: Empirical and Conceptual Questions. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Neural Correlates of Consciousness
Empirical and Conceptual Questions
Edited by Thomas Metzinger
Preface
Sample Chapter - Download PDF (24 KB)
1
Introduction: Consciousness Research at the End of the Twentieth Century
Sample Chapter - Download PDF (129 KB)
I
FOUNDATIONAL ISSUES AND CONCEPTUAL PROBLEMS
2
What Is a Neural Correlate of Consciousness?
3
The Perennial Problem of the Reductive Explainability of Phenomenal Consciousness: C. D. Broad on the Explanatory Gap
4
Prospects for a Scientific Research Program on Consciousness
5
The Evolution and Ontogeny of Consciousness
II
CANDIDATES FOR THE NCC I: REPRESENTATIONAL DYNAMICS
6
The Unconscious Homunculus
7
A Neurobiology for Consciousness
8
Phenomenal Awareness and Consciousness from a Neurobiological Perspective
9
Reentry and the Dynamic Core: Neural Correlates of Conscious Experience
III
CANDIDATES FOR THE NCC II: VISION
10
Visual Perception Without Awareness: Priming Responses by Color
11
Face Representation Without Conscious Processing
12
Space in the Brain: Different Neural Substrates for Allocentric and Egocentric Frames of Reference
13
Conscious Registration of Continuous and Discrete Visual Events
14
Imaging Conscious Vision
15
Binocular Rivalry and Human Visual Awareness
IV
CANDIDATES FOR THE NCC III: CONSCIOUSNESS, ANESTHESIA, AND THE NMDA RECEPTOR COMPLEX
16
NMDA Receptor--Mediated Computational Processes and Phenomenal Consciousness
17
How to Understand the N in NCC
18
The Role of NMDA Receptors in Consciousness: What We Learn from Anesthetic Mechanisms?
19
NMDA Receptor--Mediated Consciousness: A Theoretical Framework for Understanding the Effects of Anesthesia on Cognition?
V
TOWARD THE NEURAL CORRELATES OF SELFHOOD, AGENCY, AND SOCIAL COGNITION
20
The Subjectivity of Subjective Experience: A Representationist Analysis of the First-Person Perspective
21
Awareness of Agency: Three Levels of Analysis
22
The Acting Subject: Toward the Neural Basis of Social Cognition
Contributors
Index
Sample Chapter - Download PDF (56 KB)
◆ Metzinger, Thomas (Feb. 2003). Being No One: The Self-Model Theory of Subjectivity. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Being No One:
The Self-Model Theory of Subjectivity
Thomas Metzinger
Acknowedgments | xi | |
1. | Questions Sample Chapter - Download PDF (83 KB) |
1 |
2. | Tools I | 13 |
3. | The Representational Deep Structure of Phenomenal Experience | 107 |
4. | Neurophenomenological Case Studies I | 213 |
5. | Tools II | 265 |
6. | The Representational Deep Structure of the Phenomenal First-Person Perspective | 299 |
7. | Neurophenomenological Case Studies II | 429 |
8. | Preliminary Answers | 547 |
References | 635 | |
Name Index Sample Chapter - Download PDF (50 KB) |
663 | |
Subject Index Sample Chapter - Download PDF (129 KB) |
◈ Metzinger, Thomas (2003). The pre-scientific concept of a "soul": A neurophenomenological hypothesis about its origin. In M. Peschl (Hrsg.), Auf der Suche nach dem Konzept/Substrat der Seele. Ein Versuch aus der Perspektive der Cognitive (Neuro-) Science. Würzburg: Königshausen und Neumann.
A much better and revised version: Metzinger, Thomas (2005). Out-of-Body Experiences as the Origin of the Concept of a "Soul". Mind and Matter, 3(1): 57-84. Here is a version including color figures: [ PDF; 1,57 MB ].
◈ Meyering, Theo C. (2000). Physicalism and downward causation in psychology and the special sciences. Inquiry 43: 181-202.
■ Minati, Gianfranco, Eliano Pessa (eds.) (2002). Emergence in Complex Cognitive, Social and Biological Systems. Springer.
The systems movement is made up of many systems societies as well as of disciplinary researchers and researches, explicitly or implicitly focusing on the subject of systemics, officially introduced in the scientific community fifty years ago. Many researches in different fields have been and continue to be sources of new ideas and challenges for the systems community. To this regard, a very important topic is the one of EMERGENCE. Between the goals for the actual and future systems scientists there is certainly the definition of a general theory of emergence and the building of a general model of it.
The goal of this book, is to recall to the systems community an important challenge to be dealt with in the immediate future: the study and characterization of general features of what is commonly qualified as `emergence', chiefly in complex systems such as biological and cognitive ones. Such a topic was a fundamental one at the very beginning of the systemic movement, and to it the founding fathers, such as Von Bertalanffy, Ashby and Von Foerster, devoted most efforts. In more recent times, however, the interests shifted towards an empirical study of systemic properties characterizing human organizations, and the subject of emergence was partly abandoned. Notwithstanding, the understanding of what is emergence, and of the circumstances which allow for its occurrence within a complex system, is of crucial importance for systemics. Namely all systemic properties - the ones which allow a system to behave as a whole and not as an aggregate of constituents - are just emergent properties.
Table of contents
■ Minati, Gianfranco, Eliano Pessa, Mario Abram (eds.) (2006). Systemics of Emergence: Research and Development. Springer.
About this book
Within the General Systems Theory (GST) approach, it is possible to focus on "emergent" systemic properties (typically occurring in open, adaptive, anticipatory and chaotic systems), by stressing their specificity and their lack of reducibility into further components. In other words, emergence underlies the processes allowing the establishing of systemic properties. Research on emergence deals with experimental detection, modeling and simulation of processes giving rise to the occurrence of macroscopic (often complex and unexpected) behaviors in complex systems consisting of a large number of components. Actually such a theoretical and experimental effort relies on analytical methods, such as the ones used in modern theories of self-organization, collective-behaviors, phase transitions and artificial life. In sum, the research on emergence analyzes the engine of GST, while GST itself focuses on the general outcomes of this research, thus conceptually inducing an inter- and trans-disciplinary context.
SYSTEMICS OF EMERGENCE: Research and Development is a volume devoted to exploring the core theoretical and disciplinary research problems of emergence processes from which systems are established. It focuses on emergence as the key point of any systemic process. This topic is dealt with within different disciplinary approaches, indicated by the organization in sections: 1) Applications; 2) Biology and human care; 3) Cognitive Science; 4) Emergence; 5) General Systems; 6) Learning; 7) Management; 8) Social Systems; 9) Systemic Approach and Information Science; 10) Theoretical issues in Systemics.
The Editors and contributing authors have produced this volume to help, encourage and widen the work in this area of General Systems Research.
Table of contents
Program Committee.....xi
Contributing Authors.....xiii
Preface.....xv
Acknowledgments.....xix
OPENING LECTURE.....1
Uncertainty and Information: Emergence of Vast New Territories.....G.J. Klir.....3
APPLICATIONS.....29
Complexity in Universe Dynamic Evolution. Part 1 - Present state and future evolution.....U. Di Caprio.....31
Complexity in Universe Dynamic Evolution. Part 2 - Preceeding history.....U. Di Caprio.....51
Mistake Making Machines.....G. Minati and G. Vitiello.....67
Explicit Velocity for Modelling Surface Complex Flows with Cellular Automata and Applications.....M.V. Avolio, G.M. Crisci, D. D'Ambrosio, S. Di Gregorio, G. Iovine, V. Lupiano, R. Rongo, W. Spataro and G.A. Trunfio.....79
Analysis of Fingerprints through a Reactive Agent.....A. Montesanto, G. Tascini, P. Baldassarri and L. Santinelli.....93
User Centered Portal Design: A case study in web usability.....M.P. Penna, V. Stara and D. Costenaro.....105
BIOLOGY AND HUMAN CARE.....115
Logic and Context in Schizophrenia.....P.L. Bandinelli, C. Palma, M.P. Penna and E. Pessa.....117
The "Hope Capacity" in the Care Process and the Patient-Physician Relationship.....A. Ricciuti.....133
Puntonet 2003. A multidisciplinary and systemic approach in training disabled people within the experience of Villa S. Ignazio.....D. Fortin, V. Durini and M. Nardon.....147
Intelligence and Complexity Management: From physiology to pathology. Experimental Evidences and Theoretical Models.....P.L. Marconi.....155
Disablement, Assistive Technologies and Computer Accessibility: Hints of Analysis through a clinical approach based on the ICF model.....C. Masala and D.R. Petretto.....169
Chaos and Cultural Fashions.....S. Benvenuto.....179
COGNITIVE SCIENCE.....191
Personality and Complex Systems: An expanded view.....M. Meleddu and L.F. Scalas.....193
Complexity and Paternalism.....P. Ramazzotti.....207
A Computational Model of Face Perception.....M.P. Penna, V. Stara, M. Boi and P. Puliti.....223
The Neon Color Spreading and the Watercolor Illusion: Penomenal Links and Neural Mechanisms.....B. Pinna.....235
Usability and Man-Machine Interaction.....M.P. Penna and R. Rani.....255
Old Maps and the Watercolor Illusion: Cartography, Vision Science and Figure-Ground Segregation Principles.....B. Pinna and G. Mariotti.....261
EMERGENCE.....279
Autopoiesis and the Emergence.....L. Bich.....281
Typical Emergencies in Electric Power Systems.....U. Di Caprio.....293
Strategies of Adaptation of Man to His Environment: Projection Outside the Human Body of Social Institutions.....E.A. Nunez.....311
Emergence of the Cooperation-Competition Between Two Robots.....G. Tascini and A. Montesanto.....317
Overcoming Computationalism in Cognitive Science.....M.P. Penna....341
Physical and Biological Emergence: Are they different?.....E. Pessa.....355
GENERAL SYSTEMS.....375
Interactions Between Systems.....M.R. Abram.....377
Towards a Systemic Approach to Architecture.....V. Di Battista.....391
Music, Emergence and Pedagogical Process.....E. Pietrocini.....399
Intrinsic Uncertainty in the Study of Complex Systems: The Case of Choice of Academic Career.....M.S. Ferretti and E. Pessa.....417
A Model of Hypertextual Structure and Organization.....M.P. Penna, V. Stara, D. Costenaro and P. Puliti.....427
LEARNING.....435
Teachers in the Technological Age: A Comparison between Traditional and Hypertextual Instructional Strategies.....M.P. Penna, V. Stara and D. Costenaro.....437
The Emergence of E.Learning.....M.P. Penna, V. Stara and P. Puliti.....447
Spatial Learning in Children.....B. Lai, M.P. Penna and V. Stara....453
MANAGEMENT.....461
Dynamics of Strategy: A feedback approach to corporate strategy-making.....V. Coda and E. Mollona.....463
A Cognitive Approach to Organizational Complexity.....G. Fioretti and B. Visser.....495
Normative Commitment to the Organization, Support and Self Competence.....A. Battistelli, M. Mariani and B. Bello.....515
A Multivariate Contribution to the Study of Mobbing, Using the QAM 1.5 Questionnaire.....P. Argentero and N.S. Bonfiglio.....527
Representation in Psychometrics: Confirmatory Factor Models of Job Satisfaction in a Group of Professional Staff.....M.S. Ferretti and P. Argentero.....535
SOCIAL SYSTEMS.....549
The Impact of Email on System Identify and Autonomy: A Case Study in Self-Observation.....L. Biggiero.....551
Some Comments on Democracy and Manipulating Consent in Western Post-Democratic Societies.....G. Minati.....569
Metasystem Transitions and Sustainability in Human Organizations, Part 1 - Towards Organizational Synergetics.....G. Terenzi.....585
Metasystem Transitions and Sustainability in Human Organizations, Part 2 - A Heuristics for Global Sustainability.....G. Terenzi.....601
SYSTEMIC APPROACH AND INFORMATION SCIENCE.....613
Scale Free Graphs in Dynamic Knowledge Acquisition.....I. Licata, G. Tascini, L. Lella, A. Montesanto and W. Giordano.....615
Recent Results on Random Boolean Networks.....R. Serra and M. Villani.....625
Color-Oriented Content Based Image Retrieval.....G. Tascini, A. Montesanto and P. Pulini.....635
THEORETICAL ISSUES IN SYSTEMICS.....651
Uncertainty and the Role of the Observer.....G. Bruno, G. Minai and A. Trotta.....653
Towards a Second Systemics.....G. Minati.....667
Is Being Computational an Intrinsic Property of a Dynamical System?.....M. Giunti.....683
The Origin of Analogies in Physics.....E. Tonti.....695
Prisoner Dilemma: A model taking into account expectancies.....N.S. Bonfiglio and E. Pessa.....707
The Theory of Levels of Reality and the Difference between Simple and Tangled Hierarchies.....R. Poli.....715
General System Theory, Like-Quantum Semantics and Fuzzy Sets.....I. Licata.....723
About the Possibility of a Cartesian Theory Upon Systems, Information and Control.....P. Rocchi.....735
◇ Misteli, Tom (Oct. 15, 2001). The concept of self-organization in cellular architecture. The Journal of Cell Biology 155(2): 181-186. (doi:10.1083/jcb.200108110)
Published 15 October 2001.
Abstract: In vivo microscopy has recently revealed the dynamic nature of many cellular organelles. The dynamic properties of several cellular structures are consistent with a role for self-organization in their formation, maintenance, and function; therefore, self-organization might be a general principle in cellular organization.
Key Words: self-organization; cytoskeleton; nucleus; Golgi complex; dynamics
http://www.jcb.org/cgi/content/full/155/2/181
◈ Molenaar, Peter C.M. (Dec. 2006). Psychophysical dualism from the point of view of a working psychologist. Erkenntnis 65(1): 47-69.
▣ Montecucco, Nitamo Federico (Jan. 2006). Coherence, Brain Evolution, and the Unity of Consciousness: The evolution of Planetary Consciousness in the Light of Brain Coherence Research. World Futures 62(1 & 2): 127-133.
Abstract: The law of coherence helps us understand the physical force behind the increasing complexity of the evolutionary process, from quanta, to cells, to self-awareness and collective consciousness. The coherent electromagnetic field is the inner glue of every system, the "intelligent" energy-information communication that assures a cooperative and synergic behavior to all the components of the system, as a whole, allowing harmonious evolution and unity of consciousness. Neuropsychological experiments show that the different brain areas communicate with more or less coherence according to different states of consciousness: high values are correlated with states of psychophysical integrity and well-being, whereas low values with states of conflict and depression. If we expand isomorphically these brain discoveries, we will have four main general states of coherence: from disgregation to unity, which represents an important element, in the General System Theory, to differentiate between inanimate and animate system, and to understand how billions cells become a single living organism, and then how billions of human beings could eventually generate planetary consciousness. In this light the resolution of the global ecosystem crisis implicates human transformation from a low to a highly coherent state of consciousness. The key to the entire process seems to be the coherent nature of consciousness.
Keywords: Brain synchronization; coherence; evolution of consciousness; self-awareness; unity of consciousness
■ Moreno, Alvaro and Jon Umerez (2000). Downward Causation at the Core of Living Organization. In Peter Bøgh Andersen, Claus Emmeche, Niels Ole Finnemann and Peder Voetmann Christiansen (eds.) (2000). Downward Causation: Minds, bodies and matter. Århus(Aarhus): Aarhus University Press, pp. 99-117.
◈ Morgan, C. Lloyd (1923). Emergent Evolution. London: Williams & Norgate.
Available online http://spartan.ac.brocku.ca/~lward/morgan/Morgan_1923
◈ Morowitz, Harold J. (Apr. 2001). The epistemic paradox of mind and matter. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 929(1): 50-54.
◈ Morowitz, Harold J. (2003). The Emergence of Everything: How the World Became Complex. Oxford University Press.
◆ Morris, C.R. (1926). The notion of emergence. Aristotelian Society Supplement 6: 49-55.
■ Müller-Herold, U. (Dec. 1984). A simple model for the evolutionary emergence of novel properties. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres (Formerly Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere) 14(1-4): 523-529.
◈ Murphy, Nancey and Warren S. Brown (May 2007). Did My Neurons Make Me Do It?: Philosophical and Neurobiological Perspectives on Moral Responsibility and Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
contents
Introduction: New Approaches to Knotty Old Problems
1. Avoiding Cartesian Materialism
2. From Causal Reductionism to Self-Directed Systems
3. From Mindless to Intelligent Action
4. How Can Neural Nets Mean?
5. How Does Reason Get Its Grip on the Brain?
6. Who's Responsible?
7. Neurobiological Reductionism and Free Will
Postscript
◈ Murphy, Nancey, William R. Stoeger, SJ (eds.) (2007). Evolution and Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
contents
Introduction ,
◈ Pihlström, Sami (2002). The Re-Emergence of the Emergence Debate. Principia, Special
Issue on Emergence and Downward Causation (El-Hani, C.N. Ed.) 6: 133-181.
◈ Pikovsky, Arkady, Michael Rosenblum, Jürgen Kurths (2002). Synchronization: A Universal Concept in Nonlinear Sciences. Cambridge University Press.
▣ Pineda, David (Oct. 2006). A Mereological Characterization of Physicalism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 20(3): 243-266. (DOI: 10.1080/02698590600960929)
Abstract: Physicalism is usually understood as the claim that every empirical entity is or is determined by physical entities. The claim is however imprecise until it is clarified what are the physical entities in question. A sceptical argument in the form of a dilemma tries to show that this problem of formulation of physicalism cannot be adequately met. If we understand physical entities as the entities introduced by current physics, the resulting claim becomes most probably false. If we instead understand physical entities as those entities introduced by some future ideal physics, the claim then becomes indeterminate in content. Both horns seem equally bad. In the first part of the paper, I survey the strengths and weaknesses of different proposed solutions to this problem of formulation. In the second part, I lay out a new formulation of physicalism, partly based on a mereological principle, which overcomes the dilemma, and argue that it is a correct formulation of physicalism to the extent that it rules out clear antiphysicalist scenarios and is compatible with clear physicalist scenarios.
◆ Pinker, Steven (1997). How the Mind Works. W.W. Norton & Company.
◆ Pinker, Steven (Jan. 19, 2007). The mystery of consciousness. Time.
http://www.time.com/time/magazine/article/0,9171,1580394,00.html
▶ Pluhar, E. (1978). Emergence and reduction. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 9: 279-289.
◈ Pockett, Susan (2002). Difficulties with the electromagnetic field theory of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 9(4): 51-56.(pdf)
Abstract: The author’s version of the electromagnetic field theory of consciousness is stated briefly and then three difficulties with the theory are discussed. The first is a purely technical problem: how to measure accurately enough the spatial properties of the fields which are proposed to be conscious and then how to generate these artificially, so that the theory can be tested. The second difficulty might also be merely technical, or it might be substantive and fatal to the theory. This is that present measurements seem to show a non-constant relationship between brain-generated electromagnetic fields and sensation. The third difficulty involves the basic question of whether consciousness per se has any direct effect on the brain. As an afterword, the disproportionate contribution of synchronously firing neurons to conscious percepts is simply explained in terms of the electromagnetic field theory of consciousness.
◈ Pockett, Susan (in press). The concept of free will: philosophy, neuroscience and the law. Behavioral sciences & the law.
Available online 2007 Feb 23.
Introduction Susan Pockett, William P. Banks and Shaun Gallagher Sample Chapter - Download PDF (66 KB) |
1 | |
I | Neuroscience | 9 |
1 | The Neuroscience of Movement Susan Pockett Sample Chapter - Download PDF (129 KB) |
9 |
2 | Consciousness of Action as an Embodied Consciousness Marc Jeannerod |
25 |
3 | Intentions, Actions, and the Self Suparna Choudhury and Sarah-J. Blakemore |
39 |
4 | Free Choice and the Human Brain Richard E. Passingham and Hakwan C. Lau |
53 |
5 | Consciousness, Intentionality, and Causality Walter J. Freeman |
73 |
II | Philosophy | |
6 | Where's the Action? Epiphenomenalism and the Problem of Free Will Shaun Gallagher |
109 |
7 | Empirical Constraints on the Problem of Free Will Peter W. Ross |
125 |
8 | Toward a Dynamic Theory of Intentions Elisabeth Pacherie |
145 |
9 | Phenomenology and the Feeling of Doing: Wegner on the Conscious Will Timothy Bayne |
169 |
10 | Free Will: Theories, Analysis, and Data Alfred R. Mele |
187 |
11 | Of Windmills and Straw Men: Folk Assumptions of Mind and Action Bertram F. Malle |
207 |
III | Law and Public Policy | |
12 | Does Consciousness Cause Misbehavior? William P. Banks |
235 |
13 | Free Will as a Social Institution Wolfgang Prinz |
257 |
14 | Truth and/or Consequences: Neuroscience and Criminal Responsibility Leonard V. Kaplan |
277 |
15 | Bypassing Conscious Control: Unconscious Imitation, Media Violence, and Freedom of Speech Susan Hurley |
301 |
16 | Neurosociety Ahead? Debating Free Will in the Media Sabine Maasen |
339 |
List of Contributors Sample Chapter - Download PDF (22 KB) |
361 | |
Index Sample Chapter - Download PDF (33 KB) |
▣ Popper, Karl Raimund and John Carew Eccles (1977). The Self and Its Brain. Berlin, Heidelberg, London, New York: Springer.
■ Pribram, Karl H. (1991). Brain and perception: Holonomy and structure in figural processing. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
■ Pribram, Karl H. (Apr. 22, 2007). Holonomic Brain Theory. Scholarpedia.
http://scholarpedia.org/article/Holonomic_Brain_Theory
Karl H. Pribram
◈ Prigogine, Ilya and Isabelle Stengers (1984). Order Out of Chaos: Man's New Dialogue with Nature. New York: Bantam Books.
Ilya Prigogine (Jan. 17, 1917 - May 28, 2003)
■ Primas, Hans (1998). Emergence in Exact Natural Sciences. In G. Farre and T. Oksala (Eds.) Acta Polytechnica Scandinavica 91: 83–98.
Abstract: The context of an operational description is given by the distinction between what we consider as relevant and what as irrelevant for a particular experiment or observation. A rigorous description of a context in terms of a mathematically formulated context-independent fundamental theory is possible by the restriction of the domain of the basic theory and the introduction of a new coarser topology. Such a new topology is never given by first principles, but depends in a crucial way on the abstractions made by the cognitive apparatus or the pattern recognition devices used by the experimentalist. A consistent mathematical formulation of a higher-level theory requires the closure of the restriction of the basic theory in the new contextual topology. The validity domain of the so constructed higher-level theory intersects nontrivially with the validity domain of the basic theory: neither domain is contained in the other. Therefore, higher-level theories cannot be totally ordered and theory reduction is not transitive. The emergence of qualitatively new properties is a necessary consequence of such a formulation of theory reduction (which does not correspond to the traditional one). Emergent properties are not manifest on the level of the basic theory, but they can be derived rigorously by imposing new, contextually selected topologies upon context-independent first principles. Most intertheoretical relations are mathematically describable as singular asymptotic expansions which do not converge in the topology of the primary theory, or by choosing one of the infinitely many possible, physically inequivalent representations of the primary theory (Gelfand–Naimark–Segal-construction of algebraic quantum mechanics). As examples we discuss the emergence of shadows, inductors, capacitors and resistors from Maxwell’s electrodynamics, the emergence of order parameters in statistical mechanics, the emergence of mass as a classical observable in Galilei-relativistic theories, the emergence of the shape of molecules in quantum mechanics, the emergence of temperature and other classical observables in algebraic quantum mechanics.
Keywords: Intertheoretical relations. Higher-level theories. Singular asymptotic expansions. Gelfand–Naimark–Segal-construction. Emergence of novelty.
http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00000953/00/EmergenceInExactSciences.pdf
◈ Principia (an International Journal of Epistemology) Vol. 6, no. 1, June 2002.
Special Issue on: Emergence and Downward Causation
http://www.cfh.ufsc.br/~pricipia/
◈ Queiroz, João, Charbel Niño El-Hani (Sep. 2006). Towards a multi-level approach to the emergence of meaning processes in living systems. Acta Biotheoretica 54(3): 179-206.
Received: 5 January 2006 Accepted: 11 April 2006
◈ Rantala, Veikko (2001). Knowledge representation: two kinds of emergence. Synthese 129: 195-209.
◈ Reid, Robert G.B. (Mar. 2007). Biological Emergences: Evolution by Natural Experiment. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Biological Emergences
Evolution by Natural Experiment
Robert G. B. Reid
Series Foreword | xi | |
Preface | xiii | |
Introduction: The Re-invention of Natural Selection | 1 | |
1 | Paradigm Drift | 27 |
2 | Prologue to Emergence | 67 |
3 | Evolution by Association | 95 |
4 | The Physiological Arena | 137 |
5 | Development and Evolution | 179 |
6 | Epigenetic Mechanisms | 223 |
7 | Orthogenesis | 267 |
8 | The Re-invention of Emergence | 289 |
9 | From the Particular to the General | 329 |
10 | An Emergence Theory | 363 |
11 | A Biological Synthesis | 401 |
Notes | 437 | |
Bibliography | 465 | |
Index |
505
|
http://mitpress.mit.edu/catalog/item/default.asp?ttype=2&tid=11165&mode=toc
▶ Ripley, Charles (1984). Sperry's concept of consciousness. Inquiry 27: 399-423.
◈ Robb, David and John Heil (Dec. 18, 2003). Mental causation. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mental-causation/
◈ Rohrlich, Fritz (1997). Cognitive emergence. Philosophy of Science 64 (Proceedings): S346-358.
◈ Rosenblum, Bruce, Fred Kuttner (2006). Quantum Enigma: Physics Encounters Consciousness. Oxford University Press.
contents
1. Presenting the Enigma
2. Einstein Called it "Spooky"--and I Wish I Had Known
3. The Visit to Neg Ahne Poc: A Quantum Parable
4. Our Newtonian Worldview: A Universal Law of Motion
5. All the Rest of Classical Physics
Hello Quantum Mechanics
6. How the Quantum Was Forced on Physics
7. Schrödinger's Equation: The New Universal Law of Motion
8. One-Third of Our Economy
9. Our Skeleton in the Closet
10. Wonderful, Wonderful Copenhagen
11. Schrödinger's Controversial Cat
12. Seeking a Real World: EPR
13. Spooky Interactions: Bell's Theorem
14. What's Going On?: Interpreting the Quantum Enigma
15. The Mystery of Consciousness
16. The Mystery Meets the Enigma
17. Consciousness and the Quantum Cosmos
Suggested Readings
Index
http://www.oup.com/uk/catalogue/?ci=9780195175592
◈ Rosenberg, Alex (July 2001). On multiple realization and the special sciences. Journal of Philosophy 98(7): 365-373.
◈ Ross, Peter W. (Mar. 2001). The location problem for color subjectivism. Consciousness and Cognition 10(1): 42-58.
◈ Ross, Peter W. (Oct. 2001). Qualia and the senses. The Philosophical Quarterly 51(205): 495-511.
◈ Rudrauf, David, Antoine Lutz, Diego Cosmelli, Jean-Philippe Lachaux and Michel Le Van Quyen (2003). From Autopoiesis to neurophenomenology: Francisco Varela’s exploration of the biophysics of being. Biological Research 36(1): 27-65.
◈ Rueger, Alexander (Sep. 2000). Robust supervenience and emergence. Philosophy of Science 67(3): 466-489.
◈ Rueger, Alexander (2000). Physical emergence, Diachronic and Synchronic. Synthese 124(3): 297-322.
Abstract: This paper explicates two notions of emergencewhich are based on two ways of distinguishinglevels of properties for dynamical systems.Once the levels are defined, the strategies ofcharacterizing the relation of higher level to lower levelproperties as diachronic and synchronic emergence are the same. In each case, the higher level properties aresaid to be emergent if they are novel or irreducible with respect to the lower level properties. Novelty andirreducibility are given precise meanings in terms of the effectsthat the change of a bifurcation or perturbation parameterin the system has. (The same strategy can be applied to otherways of separating levels of properties, like themicro/macro distinction.)
◈ Rueger, Alexander (2006). Functional reduction and emergence in the physical sciences. Synthese 151(3): 335-346.
Published online: 28 July 2006
Keywords: Emergence - Functional properties - Kim’s view of reduction - Micro/macro levels - Reduction - Singular Perturbations
■ Russell, E. S. (1926). The notion of emergence. Aristotelian Society Supplement 6: 39-48.
◈ Ryan, Alex J. (Sep. 6, 2006). Emergence is Coupled to Scope, not Level. abbreviated version to be submitted to Complexity.
Since its application to systems, emergence has been explained in terms of levels of observation. This approach has led to confusion, contradiction, incoherence and at times mysticism. When the idea of level is replaced by a framework of scope, resolution and state, this confusion is dissolved. We find that emergent properties are determined by the relationship between the scope of macrostate and microstate descriptions. This establishes a normative definition of emergent properties and emergence that makes sense of previous descriptive definitions of emergence. In particular, this framework sheds light on which classes of emergent properties are epistemic and which are ontological, and identifies fundamental limits to our ability to capture emergence in formal systems.
◈ Sarkar, Sahotra (1998). Genetics and Reductionism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
◈ Savellos, Elias E. and Ümit D. Yalçin (eds.) (1995). Supervenience: New Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
◈ Sawyer, R. Keith (Dec. 1999). The emergence of creativity. Philosophical Psychology 12(4): 447-469.
◈ Sawyer, R. Keith (Nov. 2001). Emergence in Sociology: Contemporary Philosophy of Mind and Some Implications for Sociological Theory. American Journal of Sociology 107(3): 551-585.
Abstract: Many accounts of the micro-macro link use the philosophical notion of emergence to argue that collective phenomena are collaboratively created by individuals yet are not reducible to explanation in terms of individuals. However, emergence has also been invoked by methodological individualists; they accept the existence of emergent social properties yet claim that such properties can be reduced to explanations in terms of individuals and their relationships. Thus, contemporary sociological uses of emergence are contradictory and unstable. This article clarifies this situation by developing an account of emergence based in contemporary philosophy of mind. The philosophical account is used to evaluate contradictory sociological theories. Several unresolved issues facing theories of emergence in sociology are identified.
■ Sawyer, R. Keith (2002). Emergence in Psychology: Lessons from the History of Non-Reductionist Science. Human Development 45(1): 2-28 (DOI: 10.1159/000048148).
Abstract: Theories of emergence have had a longstanding influence on psychological thought. Emergentism rejects both reductionism and holism; emergentists are scientific materialists, and yet argue that reductionist explanation may not always be scientifically feasible. I begin by summarizing the history of emergence in psychology and sociology, from the mid-19th century through the mid-20th century. I then demonstrate several parallels between this history and contemporary psychology, focusing on two recent psychological movements: socioculturalism and connectionist cognitive science. Placed in historical context, both socioculturalism and connectionism are seen to be revivals of 19th and early 20th century emergentism. I then draw on this history to identify several unresolved issues facing socioculturalists and connectionists, and to suggest several promising paths for future theory.
Keywords: Cognitive science, Emergence, History, Reductionism, Socioculturalism
■ Sawyer, R. Keith (2002). Nonreductive Individualism Part I—Supervenience and Wild Disjunction. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 32(4): 537-559.
The author draws on arguments from contemporary philosophy of mind to provide an argument for sociological collectivism. This argument for nonreductive individualism accepts that only individuals exist but rejects methodological individualism. In Part I, the author presents the argument for nonreductive individualism by working through the implications of supervenience, multiple realizability, and wild disjunction in some detail. In Part II, he extends the argument to provide a defense for social causal laws, and this account of social causation does not require any commitment to intentionality or agency on the part of individuals.
■ Sawyer, R. Keith (2003). Nonreductive Individualism Part II—Social Causation. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 33(2): 203-224.
In Part I, the author argued for nonreductive individualism (NRI), an account of the individual-collective relation that is ontologically individualist yet rejects methodological individualism. However, because NRI is ontologically individualist, social entities and properties would seem to be only analytic constructs, and if so, they would seem to be epiphenomenal, since only real things can have causal power. In general, a nonreductionist account is a relatively weak defense of sociological explanation if it cannot provide an account of how social properties can participate in causal relations. In this article, the author extends NRI to address this weakness and provides an account of social causation that he refers to as supervenient causation.
Key Words: individualism • collectivism • social realism • social causation
■ Sawyer, R. Keith (2004). The Mechanisms of Emergence. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 34(2): 260-282.
This article focuses on emergence in social systems. The author begins by proposing a new tool to explore the mechanisms of social emergence: multi agent–based computer simulation. He then draws on philosophy of mind to develop an account of social emergence that raises potential problems for the methodological individualism of both social mechanism and of multi agent simulation. He then draws on various complexity concepts to propose a set of criteria whereby one can determine whether a given social mechanism generates emergent properties, in the sense that their explanation cannot be reduced to a mechanistic account of individuals and their interactions. This combined account helps to resolve the competing claims of methodological individualists and social realists. The author’s conclusion is that the scope of mechanistic explanation may be limited due to the extreme complexity of many social systems.
Key Words: emergence • mechanism • computer simulation • methodological individualism • social realism
◈ Sawyer, R. Keith (2005). Social Emergence: Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
▣ Schaffner, K.F. (1967). Approaches to reduction. Philosophy of Science 34: 137-147.
◈ Schouten, Maurice K.D. and Huib Looren de Jong (eds.) (2007). The Matter of the Mind: Philosophical Essays on Psychology, Neuroscience and Reduction. Oxford: Blackwell.
Table of contents
Contributors
Preface and Acknowledgments
1. Mind Matters: The Roots of Reductionism: Maurice Schouten and Huib Looren de Jong (Tilburg University and Vrije Universiteit, Amsterdam)
Part I: Metaphysics of Science:
2. Functionalism and Psychological Reductionism: Friends, Not Foes: Andrew Melnyk (University of Missouri-Columbia)
3. Some Metaphysical Anxieties of Reductionism: Thomas W. Polger (University of Cincinnati)
4. The Metaphysics of Mechanisms and the Challenge of the New Reductionism: Carl Gillett (Illinois Wesleyan University)
5. Reductionism, Embodiment, and the Generality of Psychology: Lawrence A. Shapiro (University of Wisconsin)
Part II: Philosophical Accounts of Reduction, Mechanism, Co-evolution:
6. Reduction without the Structures: Robert C. Richardson (University of Cincinnati)
7. Reinforcing the Three "R"s: Reduction, Reception, and Replacement: Ronald Endicott (North Carolina State University)
8. Reducing Psychology while Maintaining its Autonomy via Mechanistic Explanations: William Bechtel (University of California, San Diego)
9. Enriching Philosophical Models of Cross-Scientific Relations: Incorporating Diachronic Theories: Robert N. McCauley (Emory University)
Part III: Mechanisms of Mind:
10. Coupling, Emergence, and Explanation: Andy Clark (University of Edinburgh)
11. Is Psychological Explanation Going Extinct?: Cory D. Wright (University of California, San Diego)
12. Who Says You Can't Do a Molecular Biology of Consciousness?: John Bickle (University of Cincinnati)
13. Mind Reading and Mirror Neurons: Exploring Reduction: Huib Looren de Jong and Maurice Schouten (Vrije Universiteit, Amsterdam and Tilburg University)
Name Index
Subject Index
◈ Schröder, Jürgen (1998). Emergence: Non-deducibility or Downwards Causation? Philosophical Quarterly 48(193): 433-452.
◈ Schröder, Jürgen (2002). The supervenience argument and the generalization problem. Erkenntnis 56(3): 319-328.
▣ Schrödinger, Erwin (1944/1992). What is Life?: The Physical Aspect of the Living Cell. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Erwin Schrödinger (1887-1961)
◇ Schurz, Josef (in press). Probability and Evolution. Why the Probability Argument of Creationists is Wrong. Journal for General Philosophy of Science. (doi:10.1007/s10838-006-9020-7)
Published online: 20 April 2007
Keywords: probability - evolution - creation - complexity - self-organization - selection rule
Josef Schurz: Institut fur Chemie Physikalische Chemie, Universität Graz, Heinrichstr. 28, A-8010 Graz, Austria
◆ Schwartz, Jeffrey M., Henry P. Stapp and Mario Beauregard (Jun. 29, 2005). Quantum physics in neuroscience and psychology: a neurophysical model of mind–brain interaction. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B 360(1458): 1309-27.
Received 2 June 2004, Accepted 19 October 2004
Neuropsychological research on the neural basis of behaviour generally posits that brain mechanisms will ultimately suffice to explain all psychologically described phenomena. This assumption stems from the idea that the brain is made up entirely of material particles and fields, and that all causal mechanisms relevant to neuroscience can therefore be formulated solely in terms of properties of these elements. Thus, terms having intrinsic mentalistic and/or experiential content (e.g. 'feeling', 'knowing' and 'effort') are not included as primary causal factors. This theoretical restriction is motivated primarily by ideas about the natural world that have been known to be fundamentally incorrect for more than three-quarters of a century. Contemporary basic physical theory differs profoundly from classic physics on the important matter of how the consciousness of human agents enters into the structure of empirical phenomena. The new principles contradict the older idea that local mechanical processes alone can account for the structure of all observed empirical data. Contemporary physical theory brings directly and irreducibly into the overall causal structure certain psychologically described choices made by human agents about how they will act. This key development in basic physical theory is applicable to neuroscience, and it provides neuroscientists and psychologists with an alternative conceptual framework for describing neural processes. Indeed, owing to certain structural features of ion channels critical to synaptic function, contemporary physical theory must in principle be used when analysing human brain dynamics. The new framework, unlike its classic-physics-based predecessor, is erected directly upon, and is compatible with, the prevailing principles of physics. It is able to represent more adequately than classic concepts the neuroplastic mechanisms relevant to the growing number of empirical studies of the capacity of directed attention and mental effort to systematically alter brain function.
Keywords: mind; consciousness; brain; neuroscience; neuropsychology; quantum mechanics
The only acceptable point of view appears to be the one that recognizes both sides of reality—the quantitative and the qualitative, the physical and the psychical—as compatible with each other, and can embrace them simultaneously.
(Pauli 1955, p. 208)
http://www-physics.lbl.gov/~stapp/PTRS.pdf
◈ Scott, Alwyn C. (1995). Stairway to the Mind: The Controversial New Science of Consciousness. Springer.
▣ Scott, Alwyn C. (Apr. 1996). The hierarchical emergence of consciousness. Mathematics and Computers in Simulation 40(3-4): 481-489.
◈ Scott, Alwyn C. (1996). On quantum theories of the mind (pdf 150 KB), Journal of Consciousness Sudies 3(5-6): 484-491. For other points of view see a rebuttal by Henry Stapp (pdf 140 KB) and support from a paper by Max Tegmark (pdf 456 KB).
◈ Scott, Alwyn C. (2001). We could be siblings yet (pdf 51 KB). A review of Why Religion Matters by Houston Smith. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(9-10): 161-166.
◈ Scott, Alwyn C. (2004). Reductionism revisited (pdf 121 KB). Journal of Consciousness Studies 11(2): 51-68.
◈ Scott. Alwyn C. (2007). The Nonlinear Universe: Chaos, Emergence, Life . Springer.
◈ Seager, William (2005). Emergence and efficacy. In David Martel Johnson and Christina E. Erneling eds. The Mind as a Scientific Object: Between Brain and Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◈ Searle, John (Mar. 2007). Neuroscience, Intentionality and Free Will: Reply to Habermas. Philosophical Explorations 10(1): 69-76.
Abstract: I agree with much of Habermas's article 'The Language Game of Responsible Agency and the Problem of Free Will,' but concentrate on disagreements. (i) He is wrong to think the language game of neuroscience is somehow at odds with the language game of rational intentionality. I argue that they give different levels of description of the same system. He also has too narrow a conception of contemporary neurobiological research. (ii) He is mistaken in thinking there is a 'performative contradiction' in engaging in research that presupposes free will in order to disprove free will. (iii) His 'epistemic dualism' is irrelevant to the issue. (iv) He has some misconceptions about the world in general, especially about 'downward causation.' He seems to think that the physical world is deterministic. It is not. Quantum indeterminacy pervades the entire universe. We have the illusion of determinism because in some systems the quantum indeterminacies cancel out at the macro level. Is the brain a deterministic system? Right now we do not know.
Keywords: determinism; epistemic dualism; levels of description; neurobiology
◇ Seibt, Johanna (1995). The Myth of Substance and the Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness. Acta Analytica 11(15):
Abstract: Substance ontologists claim that substances are ontologically primary because the category of substance enjoys unique explanatory potential. Unless it can be shown that *only* substances fulfill the central explanatory tasks in ontology, this inference from explanatory success to ontological primacy amounts to a fallacy akin to the error Whitehead called 'the fallacy of misplaced concreteness.' I investigate recent prototypical arguments for substance metaphysics and try to show that some explanatory functions of substance can also be fullfilled by other ontological categories. In particular, I argue against M. Ayers that there is no reason to think that all and only substances are discrete individuals, natural wholes and logical units. I conclude that the category of substance does not provide us with a uniquely powerful explanans for the notion of logical and physical unity.
◈ Seife, Charles (2000). Cold numbers unmake the quantum mind. Science 287: 791 (Issue of Feb. 4, 2000).
◈ Shagrir, Oron (2002). Global supervenience, coincident entities and anti-individualism. Philosophical Studies 109: 171-196.
◈ Shagrir, Oron (forthcoming). Concepts of Supervenience Revisited.
▣ Shannon, Claude Elwood (1948). A mathematical theory of communication. Bell System Technical Journal 27: 379–423, 623–656.
▣ Shannon, Claude Elwood and Warren Weaver (1949). The Mathematical Theory of Communication. Urbana, Illinois: The University of Illinois Press.
▣ Shapiro, Lawrence A. (Dec. 2000). Multiple Realizations. Journal of Philosophy 97(12): 635–654.
◈ Shields, George W. (May 2001). Physicalist panexperientialism and the mind-body problem. American Journal of Theology and Philosophy 22(2): 133-154.
◈ Shoemaker, Sidney (Mar. 2002). Kim on emergence. Philosophical Studies 108(1/2): 53-63.
◈ Shrader, Warren E. (Oct. 2005). The Metaphysics of Ontological Emergence. PhD Dissertation. University of Notre Dame.
http://etd.nd.edu/ETD-db/theses/available/etd-10242005-100620/unrestricted/ShraderW1005.pdf
◈ Sider, Theodore (1999). Global Supervenience and Identity across Times and Worlds. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59: 913-937.
◇ Silberstein, Michael (1998). Emergence and the Mind-Body Problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies 5(4): 464-482.
Abstract: In the first part of the paper I argue that neither physicalism (whether its reductive or non-reductive form) nor standard forms of dualism (as well as Chalmers' fundamentalism) can provide an explanatory framework for consciousness or cognition - neither account can existence of conscious experience nor its relationship to cognition and the brain. Physicalism and fundamentalism fail to provide an explanatory framework for consciousness because they both share, at least with respect to the physical universe, the same misguided commitment to part/whole reductionism and microreductive accounts of explanation. In addition to their lack of explanatory power, both physicalism and fundamentalism have well known absurd and troubling metaphysical consequences such as eliminativism and epiphenomenalism. In the second section of the paper I advocate a position I call radical emergence, arguing that microphysics (especially quantum mechanics) provides strong empirical evidence for emergence. I show that emergence provides a viable alternative for explaining consciousness and cognition - an alternative that has none of the awkward metaphysical consequences of either physicalism or fundamentalism.
◈ Silberstein, Michael and John McGeever (Apr. 1999). The search for ontological emergence. The Philosophical Quarterly 49: 182-200. (doi:10.1111/1467-9213.00136)
Abstract: We survey and clarify some recent appearances of the term 'emergence'. We distinguish epistemological emergence, which is merely a limitation of descriptive apparatus, from ontological emergence, which should involve causal features of a whole system not reducible to the properties of its parts, thus implying the failure of part/whole reductionism and of mereological supervenience for that system. Are there actually any plausible cases of the latter among the numerous and various mentions of 'emergence' in the recent literature? Quantum mechanics seems to offer one, in the Bell properties of entangled particles, but other apparently promising candidates, such as non-linear dynamical systems investigated by complexity studies and chaos theory, seem on careful analysis to display only epistemological emergence. We examine the consequences for physicalism of admitting ontological emergence in the micro-physical.
◇ Silberstein, Michael (Sep./Oct. 2001). Converging on Emergence: consciousness, causation and explanation. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(9-10): 61-98.
Abstract: I will argue that emergence is an empirically plausible and unique philosophical/ scientific framework for bridging the ontological gap and the explanatory gap with respect to phenomenal consciousness. On my view the ontological gap is the gap between fundamental ingredients/parts of reality that are not conscious (such as particles and fields) and beings/wholes (such as ourselves) that are conscious. The explanatory gap is the current lack of a philosophical/scientific theory that explains how non-conscious parts can become conscious wholes. Both gaps are of course conceptual as well as empirical in nature. Section I will be devoted to these issues as well as providing other general criteria for an account of consciousness. In section II, different types of emergence will be defined in the context of a more general taxonomy of reduction and emergence. Emergentism about consciousness becomes much more plausible when we see that the ancient ‘atomism’ (i.e., mereological and nomological supervenience) that drives physicalism on one end, and fundamental property dualism on the other, is probably false. Backing up this claim will be the primary burden of section III. In section IV I will conjecture that phenomenal consciousness is mereologically and perhaps nomologically emergent from neurochemical/ quantum processes, just as many other properties are so emergent. In section V I defend my view of emergence against the objections that: (1) it cannot bridge the explanatory/ontological gap between matter and consciousness and (2) it cannot account for the causal efficacy of consciousness in itself. Finally, in section VI, there is speculation about where all of this might take us in the future.
◈ Silberstein, Michael (2002). Reduction, Emergence and Explanation. In Peter Machamer and Michael Silberstein (eds.) Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science. Oxford: Blackwell.
◇ Silberstein, Michael (2006). Emergence, Theology and the Manifest Image. In Philip Clayton and Zachary Simpson (eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Religion and Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◇ Silberstein, Michael (2006). In Defence of Ontological Emergence and Mental Causation. In Philip Clayton and Paul Davies (eds.) The Re-Emergence of Emergence: The Emergentist Hypothesis from Science to Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◇ Silberstein, Michael (forthcoming). Consciousness, Emergence and Mereology. In Hans Burkhardt , Johanna Seibt and Guido Imaguire (eds.) Handbook of Mereology. Philosophia Verlag.
◇ Silberstein, Michael (forthcoming). Emergence and Consciousness. In Oxford Companion to Consciousness.
◈ Silberstein, Michael (forthcoming). Contextual Emergence: On the Relational Nature of Reality.
◈ Skarda, C.A. and Walter J. Freeman (1987). How Brains Make Chaos in Order to Make Sense of the World. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (June): 161-173.
◈ Skarda, C.A. and Walter J. Freeman (1990). Chaos and the New Science of the Brain. Concepts in Neuroscience 1(2): 275-285.
◈ Slors, Marc (1997). Why functional properties can be emergent: An argument against Kim. Intellectica 25(2): 59-65.
▣ Smart, J.J.C. (1981). Physicalism and emergence. Neuroscience 6: 109-113.
◈ Smedes, Taede A. (2004―2005). Emergence, Materialism, and Worldviews: A Review Article. Tradition & Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical 31(1): 36-41.
www.missouriwestern.edu/orgs/polanyi/
Abstract: This review article deals with four recent books exploring issues of emergence and self-organization. Three of these also deal with issues of materialism and religious worldviews, while one charts the history and philosophical unerpinnings of emergentist thought.
Key Words: chaos theory; complexity; emergence; Intelligent Design; materialism; Polanyi, Michael; reductionism; self-organization
◈ Smith, Kerri (2007). Looking for hidden signs of consciousness. Nature 446(7134): 355 (Issue of 22 March 2007).
A 'brain-activity' test for patients in a vegetative state has divided neurologists.
◈ Smythies, John (Mar. 2003). Space, time and consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 10(3): 47-56.
This paper describes a new theory of consciousness based on previous work by C.D. Broad, H.H. Price, Andrei Linde and others. This hypothesis states that the Universe consists of three fundamental entities — space-time, matter and consciousness, each with their own degrees of freedom. The paper pays particular attention to three areas that impact on this theory: (1) the demonstration by neuroscience and psychophysics that we do not perceive the world as it actually is but as the brain computes it most probably to be; (2) the need to delineate between phenomenal space-time and physical space-time. Recent theories in physics that suggest that the Universe has more than three spatial dimensions are relevant here; (3) the role of consciousness in the block Universe described by Special Relativity. The integration of these topics suggests a new physical theory of the nature of consciousness.
■ Spencer-Smith, Richard (1995). Reductionism and emergent properties. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 95: 113-29.
▣ Sperry, Roger Wolcott (1969). A modified concept of consciousness. Psychological Review 76: 532-536. Reprinted In: M. H. Marx and F. E. Gradson (eds.) (1976). Theories in Contemporary Psychology, pp. 451-457. New York: MacMillan Publ.Co., Inc.
▣ Sperry, Roger Wolcott (1970). An objective approach to subjective experience: Further explanation of a hypothesis. Psychological Review 77: 585-590.
▣ Sperry, Roger Wolcott (1976). Mental phenomena as causal determinants in brain function. In: Gordon G. Globus, Grover Maxwell and Irwin Savodnik (eds.) Consciousness and the Brain: A Scientific and Philosophical Inquiry. New York: Plenum Press.
▣ Sperry, Roger Wolcott (1980). Mind-brain interaction: mentalism, yes; dualism, no. Neuroscience 5: 195-206. Reprinted in A.D. Smith, R. Llanas and P.G. Kostyuk (eds.) Commentaries in the Neurosciences. Oxford: Pergamon Press, pp. 651-662 (1980).
◆ Sperry, Roger Wolcott (Jun. 1986). Macro- versus Micro-Determinism. Philosophy of Science 53(2): 265-270.
▣ Sperry, Roger Wolcott (1987). Consciousness and causality. In: Richard L. Gregory (ed.) The Oxford Companion to the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 164-166.
▣ Sperry, Roger Wolcott (Spring 1991). In defense of mentalism and emergent interaction. The Journal of Mind and Behavior 12(2): 221-245.
The mentalist mind-brain model is defended against alleged weaknesses. I argue that the perceived failings are based mostly on misinterpretation of mentalism and emergent interaction. Considering the paradigmatic concepts at issue and broad implications, I try to better clarify the misread mentalist view, adding more inclusive detail, relevant background, further analysis, and comparing its foundational concepts with those of the new cognitive paradigm in psychology. A changed "emergent interactionist" form of causation is posited that combines traditional microdeterminism with emergent "top-down" control. This emergent form of causation has wide application to causal explanation in general and is hypothesized to be the key common precursor for the consciousness (cognitive) revolution and subsequent boom in new worldviews, "systems thinking," emerging new paradigms, and other transformative developments of the 1970s and 1980s.
☞ see Larry R. Vandervert's argument (1991) against Roger Sperry's mentalism and emergent interactionism.
▣ Sperry, Roger Wolcott (Summer 1992). Turnabout on consciousness: a mentalist view. Journal of Mind and Behavior 13(3): 259-280.
Conceptual foundations for the changeover from behaviorism to mentalism are reviewed in an effort to better clarify frequently contested and misinterpreted features. The new mentalist tenets which I continue to support have been differently conceived to be a form of dualism, mind-brain identity theory, functionalism, nonreductive physical monism, dualist interactionism, emergent interactionism, and various other things. This diversity and contradiction are attributed to the fact that the new mentalist paradigm is a distinctly new position that fails to fit traditional philosophic dichotomies. Formerly opposed features from previous polar alternatives become merged into a novel unifying synthesis, an unambiguous description of which demands redefinition of old terms or/and the invention of new terminology. The present analysis and interpretation are backed by statements from the early papers.
◆ Sperry, Roger Wolcott (Apr. 1, 1995). The Riddle of Consciousness and the Changing Scientific WorldView. Journal of Humanistic Psychology 35(2): 7-33.
Centuries-old determinist traditions of scientific materialism are currently challenged in an unprecedented outburst during the past two decades of emerging new paradigms, new worldview "visions," new approaches to consciousness and to reality, and other transformative trends including an all-time high in favor of holism over reductionism. These revisionary developments are traced to sources in the preceding cognitive revolution and its changed concepts of consciousness and causation. Anew reciprocal "two-way" mode of causal determinism, required to shift mental states into an ineliminable causal role, is a common underlying factor. This bidirectional model is upheld to be a more complete and adequate paradigm for all casual explanation and understanding, giving science a new approach to the ultimate nature and meaning of existence with a new set of answers to some of today's thorniest issues.
◈ Spurrett, David, David Papineau (Jan, 1999). A note on the completeness of 'physics'. Analysis 59(1): 25-29.
■ Stace, W.T. (May 1939). Novelty, Indeterminism, and Emergence. The Philosophical Review 48(3): 296-310.
First three paragraphs:
The purpose of this paper is entirely analytical. It is not my aim to put forward any positive or constructive thesis. My object is, if possible, to introduce some measure of clarity into what seems to me to be a fog of vague ideas connected with the concept of novelty as that concept is found in the writings of such authors as Bergson, William James, Samuel Alexander, and other contemporary philosophers. I simply want to try to help in clearing up what seems to me to be a sphere of very confused thinking.
Before entering on the detail of this I want to make three introductory remarks. First, the concept of novelty in contemporary philosophy (except perhaps in Alexander) is part and parcel of a philosophical revolt against the overweening pretensions of science. Science finds, or used to find, the world completely governed by law. All events are reduced to cases of causal or functional determination. This means, it is alleged, that there can be no genuine novelty in the world. We shall have a mechanical universe, an eternal repetition of unalterable sequences, the everlasting turning of wheels upon wheels. All change is mere rearrangement of old elements in new patterns. The end is foreseeable in the beginning, is contained in the beginning. The universe cannot produce anything which was not implicitly present from the very beginning, that is, it cannot produce any novelty. The concept of novelty in philosophy is a revolt against this mechanical view of the world which is the product of science.
Secondly, it is a revolt based upon an emotional revulsion. The philosophers of novelty dislike the scientific picture. They desire a world in which what they call genuine novelty shall be possible. And because they wish for such a world they attempt to prove that the world really is of this sort. I do not want to be considered here as making a cheap accusation of wishful thinking. Their objections may, for all I know, be philosophically justifiable. I merely wish that this background of emotional revulsion be noted.
◈ Stalnaker, Robert (1996). Varieties of Supervenience. In James Tomberlin (ed.) Philosophical Perspectives 10: Metaphysics. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers. pp. 221-241.
◇ Stapp, Henry P. (Nov. 2005). Quantum Interactive Dualism: An Alternative to Materialism. Journal of Consciousness Studies 12(11): 43-58. (Reprinted in Zygon 41(2) September 2006. 599-615)
Abstract: René Descartes proposed an interactive dualism that posits an interaction between the mind of a human being and some of the matter located in his or her brain. Isaac Newton subsequently formulated a physical theory based exclusively on the material/physical part of Descartes’ ontology. Newton’s theory enforced the principle of the causal closure of the physical, and the classical physics that grew out of it enforces this same principle. This classical theory purports to give, in principle, a complete deterministic account of the physically described properties of nature, expressed exclusively in terms of these physically described properties themselves. Orthodox contemporary physical theory violates this principle in two separate ways. First, it injects random elements into the dynamics. Second, it allows, and also requires, abrupt probing actions that disrupt the mechanistically described evolution of the physically described systems. These probing actions are called Process 1 interventions by von Neumann. They are psycho-physical events. Neither the content nor the timing of these events is determined either by any known law, or by the afore-mentioned random elements. Orthodox quantum mechanics considers these events to be instigated by choices made by conscious agents. In von Neumann’s formulation of quantum theory each such intervention acts upon the state of the brain of some conscious agent. Thus orthodox von Neumann contemporary physics posits an interactive dualism similar to that of Descartes. But in this quantum version the effects of the conscious choices upon our brains are controlled, in part, by the known basic rules of quantum physics. This theoretically specified mind–brain connection allows many basic psychological and neuropsychological findings associated with the apparent physical effectiveness of our conscious volitional efforts to be explained in a causal and practically useful way. The intent of this paper is to give an updated account of the author’s developing theory that is clearer than before, focused on the positive, and suitable for non-specialist readers.
◈ Stapp, Henry P. (Dec. 2006). Quantum interactive dualism, II: The Libet and Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen causal anomalies. Erkenntnis 65(1): 117-142.
Published online: 17 October 2006
Abstract: Replacing faulty nineteenth century physics by its orthodox quantum successor converts the earlier materialist conception of nature to a structure that does not enforce the principle of the causal closure of the physical. The quantum laws possess causal gaps, and these gaps are filled in actual scientific practice by inputs from our streams of consciousness. The form of the quantum laws permits and suggests the existence of an underlying reality that is built not on substances, but on psychophysical events, and on objective tendencies for these events to occur. These events constitute intrinsic mind-brain connections. They are fundamental links between brain processes described in physical terms and events in our streams of consciousness. This quantum ontology confers upon our conscious intentions the causal efficacy assigned to them in actual scientific practice, and creates a substance-free interactive dualism. This putative quantum ontology has previously been shown to have impressive explanatory power in both psychology and neuroscience. Here it is used to reconcile the existence of physically efficacious conscious free will with causal anomalies of both the Libet and Einstein–Rosen–Podolsky types. This article is a sequel to Stapp [2005, Journal of Consciousness Studies 12(11), 43–58] but strives to be largely self-contained.
◈ Stephan, Achim (1992). Emergence – A Systematic View on its Historical Facets. Published pp. 25-48 in: Ansgar Beckermann, Hans Flohr, Jaegwon Kim (eds.) Emergence or Reduction? ― Essays on the Prospects of Nonreductive Physicalism. Berlin, New York: de Gruyter.
◈ Stephan, Achim (1997). Armchair Arguments against Emergentism. Erkenntnis 46(3): 305-314.
http://www.cogsci.uni-osnabrueck.de/~acstepha/Amchair_Arguments_Erkenntnis_46_(1997).pdf
◈ Stephan, Achim (1998). Varieties of Emergence in Artificial and Natural Systems. Zeitschrift für Naturforschung 53c: 639-656.
◈ Stephan, Achim (1999). Varieties of Emergentism. Evolution and Cognition 5: 49-59.
http://www.cogsci.uni-osnabrueck.de/~acstepha/Varieties_of_Emergentism_(1999).pdf
◈ Stephan, Achim (1999). Emergenz: Von der Unvorhersagbarkeit zur Selbstorganisation. Dresden and München: Dresden University Press.
◈ Stephan, Achim (2002a). Emergence, Irreducibility, and Downward Causation. Grazer Philosophische Studien 65 (Special Topic: Mental Causation, Multiple Realization, and Emergence): 77-93.
http://www.cogsci.uni-osnabrueck.de/~acstepha/Grazer_Philosophische_Studien_65_(2002).pdf
◈ Stephan, Achim, Hans Lenk (2002b). On Levels and Types of Complexity and Emergence. Published pp. 13-28 in: Evandro Agazzi and Luisa Montecucco (eds.) Complexity and Emergence. (Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the International Academy of the Philosophy of Science. Bergamo, Italy 9 - 13 May 2001). New Jersey, London: World Scientific.
◈ Stephan, Achim (2002c). Emergence. Published pp. 1108-1115 in: L. Nadel (ed.) Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science. Vol. 1. London: Macmillan.
◈ Stephan, Achim (2004). Phenomenal Emergence. Networks. Rivista di filosofia dell'intelligenza artificiale e scienze cognitive – A journal of the philosophy of artificial intelligence and cognitive sciences 3-4: 91-102.
http://www.cogsci.uni-osnabrueck.de/~acstepha/Phenomenal_Emergence_Networks_3-4_(2004).pdf
http://www.swif.uniba.it/lei/ai/networks
◈ Stephan, Achim (2006). The dual role of ‘emergence’ in the philosophy of mind and in cognitive science. Synthese 151(3): 485-498.
Published online: 8 August 2006
Keywords: Artifical life - Connectionism - Emergence - Qualia - Reductive explanation - Robotics
▣ Stöckler, Manfred (1990). Emergenz. Bausteine für eine Begriffsexplikation. Conceptus 24(63): 7-24.
▣ Stöckler, Manfred (1991). A Short History of Emergence and Reductionism. In Evandro Agazzi (ed.) The Problem of Reductionism in Science. (71-90). Dordrecht, NL: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
▣ Stöckler, Manfred (1991). Reductionism and the New Theories of Self-Organization. In Gerhard Schurz, Georg J.W. Dorn (eds.) Advances in Scientific Philosophy, Poznan Studies 24: 233-254.
◈ Stoljar, Daniel (Mar. 2001). Two conceptions of the physical. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXII, No. 2: 253-281.
◇ Storch, Maja, Benita Cantieni, Gerald Hüther and Wolfgang Tschacher (2006). Embodiment: Die Wechselwirkung von Körper und Psyche verstehen und nutzen. [Embodiment: Understanding and Using the Mutual Relationship. between Body and Mind]. Bern, Switzerland: Huber.
Warum fällt es vielen Menschen so schwer, achtsam mit dem eigenen Körper umzugehen? Warum ist das Befassen mit dem eigenen Körper oft mit Peinlichkeit besetzt? Warum gilt nur als intelligent, wer Würfel im Raum drehen kann und lange Wörterlisten auswendig lernen? Warum geben Menschen die Autorität für ihren physischen Körper so bereitwillig ab an eine Wissenschaft, die ihn aufteilt in scheinbar unzusammenhängende Einzelteile?
Maja Storch, Benita Cantieni, Gerald Hüther und Wolfgang Tschacher gehen in «Embodiment» diesen Fragen nach und kommen einmütig zum Schluss: Es ist höchste Zeit, das wichtigste Erfahrungsinstrument des Menschen zurückzuerobern: den Körper. Sie fordern, das Prinzip Embodiment zu berücksichtigen. Wer Menschen berät, therapiert, erforscht, muss immer auch den Körper einbeziehen.
Maja Storch beleuchtet, warum und wie die Psyche im Körper wohnt.
Wolfgang Tschacher zeigt auf, weshalb die Abspaltung des Geistes vom Körper nicht funktionieren kann.
Gerald Hüther schildert, wie sich das gut funktionierende Gehirn und der gut funktionierende Körper gegenseitig bedingen.
Benita Cantieni liefert schliesslich das anatomische Angebot: Richten Sie sich auf, richten Sie sich in Ihrem Körper ein.
Mehr auch unter www.ismz.ch
http://www.hogrefe.de/?mod=detail_bern&ISBN=978-3-456-84323-0&PHPSESSID=6qr6aob4q89ghne61n8nqo1092
◈ Strogatz, Steven (2003). Sync: How Order Emerges From Chaos in the Universe, Nature, and Everyday Life. New York: Hyperion.
◇Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical SciencesVolume 36, Issue 2, Pages 233-464 (June 2005).
Mechanisms in biology
Edited by Carl F. Craver, Lindley Darden
Introduction
Pages 233-244
Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden
Mechanisms of life in the seventeenth century: Borelli, Perrault, Régis
Pages 245-260
Dennis Des Chene
Mechanism, vitalism and organicism in late nineteenth and twentieth-century biology: the importance of historical context
Pages 261-283
Garland E. Allen
Darwinism and mechanism: metaphor in science
Pages 285-302
Michael Ruse
Adaptive speciation: the role of natural selection in mechanisms of geographic and non-geographic speciation
Pages 303-326
Jason M. Baker
Thinking about evolutionary mechanisms: natural selection
Pages 327-347
Jr., Robert A. Skipper and Roberta L. Millstein
Relations among fields: Mendelian, cytological and molecular mechanisms
Pages 349-371
Lindley Darden
Beyond reduction: mechanisms, multifield integration and the unity of neuroscience
Pages 373-395
Carl F. Craver
Regularities and causality; generalizations and causal explanations
Pages 397-420
Jim Bogen
Explanation: a mechanist alternative
Pages 421-441
William Bechtel and Adele Abrahamsen
Modeling mechanisms
Pages 443-464
Stuart Glennan
◈ Sudakov, K.V. (2001). "Imprints of Reality" in the systems mechanisms of brain activity. Neuroscience and Behavioral Physiology 31(6): 561-571.
◇ Suster, Danilo (1995). Modality and Supervenience. Acta Analytica 10(15):
Abstract: According to the thesis of modal supervenience it is impossible that two objects be alike in their actual properties but differ in their modal properties. Some have argued that the concept of supervenience is inapplicable to the modal-actual case. Some have argued that the thesis of modal supervenience is trivially true. These arguments are refuted; a thesis of the supervenience of the modal on the actual is meaningful and nontrivial. The significance of the thesis is nevertheless limited by the problem of finding a nonmodal specification for the purported subvenient properties.
▣ Symons, John and Francisco Calvo Garzón (eds.) (forthcoming in Mar. 31, 2008). The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Psychology. Routledge.
Table of Contents
Introduction Paco Calvo and John Symons
Part 1: Historical Background
1. Rationalist Roots of Modern Psyhology Gary Hatfield
2. Empirist Roots of Modern Psychology Raymond Martin
3. Origins of Experimental Psychology
Part 2: The Status of Psychological Theories
4. Is Folk Psychology a Theory? Ian Ravenscroft
5. What is a Psyhological Explanation William Betchel & Cory Wright
6. The Interface Bewteen Neuroscience and Psychology Valerie Hardcastle
Part 3: Modeling the Mind : The Battle of the ‘isms’
7. Behavourism David Braddon-Mitchell
8. Cognitivism Alan Garnham
9. Computational Functionalism Tom Polger
10. Connectionism Noel Sharkey
11. Dynamicism Gregor Schöner
12. Interactivism Mark Bickhard
Part 4: Behavior, Development and the Brain
13. Conceptual Problems in Statistics, Testing and Experimentation David Danks
14. Imaging Technologies Geraint Rees
15. Neural Mehanisms Carl Craver
16. Cellular and Sub-Cellular Neuroscience John Bickle
17. Evolutionary Models in Psychology Michael Wheeler
18. Development and Learning Aarre Laakso
19. Embodied Cognition and the Extended Mind Ken Aizawa
20. Actiona and Mind Alfred Mele
Part 5: Thought and Language
21. The Many Problems of Representation Zoltan Dienes
22. Naturalising Content Dan Ryder
23. Language and Thought Susan Schneider
24. Modularity Verena Gottschling
25. Nativism Richard Samuels
26. Non-Human Minds and Languages Colin Allen
27. Mind Reading Joseph Cruz
28. Representation and the Brain Art Markman
Part 6: Perception and Consciousness
29. Consciousness Timothy Bayne
30. Individuating the Senses Brian Keeley
31. Vision Patricia Churchland & John Jacobson
32. Color Jonathan Cohen
33. Audition Casey O'Callaghan
34. Attention Christopher Mole
Part 7: The Inner World
35. Introspection Jordi Fernández
36. Memory Mark Rowlands
37. Dreams John Sutton
38. Emotion Anthony Atkinson
39. The Unconscious/Freud Edward Erwin
40. Temporality Rick Grush
Part 8: Psychology and the Self
41. Personal Identity Marya Schechtman
42. Emodiment in Schizophrenia Giovanni Stanghellini
43. Confabulation William Hirstein
44. Aphasis Daniel Kolak
45. (Propositional) Imagination Shaun Nichols
46. Moral Judgements Jennifer Nado, Daniel Kelly and Stephen Stich
47. Buddhist Perspectives Owen Flanagan
A Glossary for Philosophy of Psychology Paco Calvo and John Symons
◈ Synthese Volume 151, Number 3, 2006년 8월.
Guest Editor: Max Kistler
Specaial Issue on:
New Perspectives on Reduction and Emergence in Physics, Biology and Psychology
◈ Tegmark, Max (Apr. 2000). Importance of quantum decoherence in brain processes. Physical Review E 61(4): 4194-4206.
Received 6 July 1999
Based on a calculation of neural decoherence rates, we argue that the degrees of freedom of the human brain that relate to cognitive processes should be thought of as a classical rather than quantum system, i.e., that there is nothing fundamentally wrong with the current classical approach to neural network simulations. We find that the decoherence time scales (∼10-13–10-20 s) are typically much shorter than the relevant dynamical time scales (∼10-3–10-1 s), both for regular neuron firing and for kinklike polarization excitations in microtubules. This conclusion disagrees with suggestions by Penrose and others that the brain acts as a quantum computer, and that quantum coherence is related to consciousness in a fundamental way.
◈ Tegmark, Max (Oct. 1, 2000). Why the brain is probably not a quantum computer. Information Sciences 128(3-4): 155-179.
◈ Thompson, Evan T. and Francisco J. Varela (2001). Radical Embodiment: Neuronal Dynamics and Consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Science 5: 418-425.
◈ Thompson, Evan T. (2004). Life and Mind: From autopoiesis to neurophenomenology. A tribute to Francisco Varela. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 3(4): 381-398.
◈ Thompson, Evan T. (Mar. 26, 2007). Mind In Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of the Mind. Harvard University Press.
http://www.hup.harvard.edu/catalog/THOMIN.html
Evan Thompson
◈ Thompson, Evan T. (forthcoming). Buddha and the Brain: Contemplative Insight and the Neuroscienece of Consciousness.
◇ Tschacher, Wolfgang and Hermann Haken (Apr. 2007). Intentionality in non-equilibrium systems? The functional aspects of self-organized pattern formation. New Ideas in Psychology Volume 25, Issue 1: 1-15. (doi:10.1016/j.newideapsych.2006.09.002)
Available online 7 November 2006.
Abstract: Psychology is frequently confronted with mind–body issues—is there a way by which mentalist and physical approaches to cognition can be integrated? Can the intentional attributes of mind be understood in scientific terms? The authors propose that synergetics, the theory of non-linear complex systems, offers steps towards a possible solution to this conundrum. In particular, we maintain that an essential property of self-organized pattern formation lies within its functionality, this being the ability to optimize, respond and adapt ‘meaningfully’ to environmental constraints. Patterns become functional because they consume in a most efficient manner the gradients which cause their evolution, thereby making synergetic pattern formation appear ‘intentional’. We therefore posit that self-organization phenomena may afford basic explanations for the adaptive, intentional and purposive behavior of many complex systems, in particular of cognitive systems. This present approach elaborates on the second law of thermodynamics.
Keywords: Cognition; Gradients; Intentionality; Mind–body problem; Self-organization; Synergetics
◈ Tuszynski, Jack A. (ed.) (2006). The Emerging Physics of Consciousness. Springer.
About this book
Consciousness is one of the major unsolved problems in science. How do the feelings and sensations making up conscious experience arise from the concerted actions of nerve cells and their associated synaptic and molecular processes? Can such feelings be explained by modern science, or is there an entirely different kind of explanation needed? And how can this seemingly intractable problem be approached experimentally? How do the operations of the conscious mind emerge out of the specific interactions involving billions of neurons? This multi-authored book seeks answers to these questions within a range of physically based frameworks, i.e, the underlying assumption is that consciousness can be understood using the intellectual potential of modern physics and other sciences. There are a number of theories of consciousness in existence, some of which are based on classical physics while some others require the use of quantum concepts. The latter ones have drawn a lot of criticism from the present-day scientific establishment while simultaneously claiming that classical approaches are doomed to failure. This book presents the reader with a spectrum of opinions from both sides of this on-going scientific debate, letting him/her decide which of these approaches are most likely to succeed.
http://www.springer.com/east/home/generic/search/results?SGWID=5-40109-22-52096966-0
contents
1 The Path Ahead --- Jack A. Tuszynski, Nancy Woolf
2 Consciousness and Quantum Physics: Empirical Research on the Subjective Reduction of the Statevector --- Dick J. Bierman, Stephen Whitmarsh
3 Microtubules in the Cerebral Cortex: Role in Memory and Consciousness --- Nancy J. Woolf
4 Towards Experimental Tests of Quantum Effects in Cytoskeletal Proteins --- Andreas Mershin, Hugo Sanabria, John H. Miller, Dharmakeerthna Nawarathna, Efthimios M.C. Skoulakis, Nikolaos E. Mavromatos, Alexadre A. Kolomenskii, Hans A. Schuessler, Richard F. Luduena, Dimitri V. Nanopoulos
5 Physicalism, Chaos and Reductionism --- Alwyn Scott
6 Consciousness, Neurobiology and Quantum Mechanics: The Case for a Connection --- Stuart Hameroff
7 Life, Catalysis and Excitable Media: A Dynamic Systems Approach to Metabolism and Cognition --- Christopher James Davia
8 The Dendritic Cytoskeleton as a Computational Device: An Hypothesis --- Avner Priel, Jack A. Tuszynski, Horacion F. Cantiello
9 Recurrent Quantum Neural Network and its Applications --- Laxmidhar Behera, Indrani Kar, Avshalom C. Elitzur
10 Microtubules as a Quantum Hopfield Network --- Elizabeth C. Behrman, K. Gaddam, J.E. Steck, S.R. Skinner
11 Consciousness and Quantum Brain Dynamics --- Gordon Globus
12 The CEMI Field Theory: Seven Clues to the Nature of Consciousness --- Johnjoe McFadden
13 Quantum Cosmology and the Hard Problem of the Conscious Brain --- Chris King
14 Consciousness and Logic in a Quantum Computing Universe --- Paola Zizzi
Index
■ Van Bouwel, Jeroen (Dec. 2004). Individualism and Holism, Reduction and Pluralism: A Comment on Keith Sawyer and Julie Zahle. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 34(4): 527-535.
Received 13 November 2003
Commenting on recent articles by Keith Sawyer and Julie Zahle, the author questions the way in which the debate between methodological individualists and holists has been presented and contends that too much weight has been given to metaphysical and ontological debates at the expense of giving attention to methodological debates and analysis of good explanatory practice. Giving more attention to successful explanatory practice in the social sciences and the different underlying epistemic interests and motivations for providing explanations or reducing theories (which ask for different kinds of explanatory information to be found on the social or on the individual level) might lead to real progress in the debate on methodological individualism, and away from the unending battles of (metaphysical) intuitions.
Keywords: methodological individualism; nonreductive materialism; pluralism; pragmatics of explanation
■ Van Bouwel, Jeroen (2006). De idee van emergentie in de sociologie: perspectieven en problemen(The idea of emergence in sociology: perspectives and problems). Tijdschrift voor Sociologie (Themanummer over causaliteit) 27(4): 337-350.
Recently the philosophical concept of emergence has been used in sociology to understand and defend social causation and nonreductive individualism (e.g., Sawyer, 2001, 2003 and forthcoming). In this paper, I want to analyse how the concept of emergence helps us illuminating the individual-collective relation in sociology, paying attention to the analogies with philosophy of mind. Subsequently, some questions will be raised about Keith Sawyer's use of emergence in his defence of sociological explanation. Therefore, it will be important to distinguish ontological from epistemological emergence. Where Sawyer focuses on ontological emergence, I will argue that sociological explanation might better be defended by putting emphasis on pragmatic aspects of explanation (c.f., Van Bouwel, 2004; Van Bouwel and Weber, 2002) and considering emergence as an epistemological category.
■ Van Bouwel, Jeroen (200+). Why social emergence? Discussing the use of analytical metaphysics in social theory. In: R. Vanderbeeken and B. D’Hooghe (eds.) (200+). Worldviews, Science and Us: Studies of Analytical Metaphysics. A Selection of Topics From a Methodological Perspective. Singapore: World Scientific Publishing Company (forthcoming).
■ Van Bouwel, Jeroen and Erik Weber (Dec. 2002). Remote Causes, Bad Explanations? Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 32(4): 437-449 (doi:10.1111/1468-5914.00197).
◈ Van Cleve, James 1990. Mind-Dust or Magic? Panpsychism Versus Emergence. Philosophical Perspectives 4: 215-226.
First three paragraphs:
If evolution is to work smoothly, consciousness in some shape must have been present at the very origin of things. Accordingly, we find that the more clear-sighted evolutionary philosophers are beginning to posit it there. Each atom of the nebula, they suppose, must have had an aboriginal atom of consciousness linked with it.
So wrote William James in the section of The Principle of Psychology entitled "Evolutionary Psychology Demands a Mind-Dust." The mind-dust argument, or something like it, has recently been revived by Thomas Nagel. In Nagel's version, the argument runs as follows:
1. Human beings are complex systems composed entirely of matter. (Material Composition, or Anti-Dualism)
2. Mental properties are not logically implied by any physical properties. (Anti-Reductivism)
3. Human beings do have mental properties. (Anti-Eliminativism)
4. There are no emergent properties. That is to say, all properties of a complex system that are not relations between it and something else derive from the properties of its constituents and their mode of combination. (Anti-Emergence)
◈ Van De Laar, Tjeerd (Oct. 2006). Dynamical Systems Theory as an Approach to Mental Causation. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 37(2): 307-332.
■ Vandervert, Larry R. (Spring 1991). A Measurable and Testable Brain-Based Emergent Interactionism: An Alternative to Sperry's Mentalist Emergent Interactionism. The Journal of Mind and Behavior 12(2): 210-220.
Possible measurement and testability weaknesses in Sperry's mind-supervenient emergent interactionism "argument by analogy" model are described. An alternative brain-supervenient interactionism that addresses the weaknesses of Sperry's mind-brain model is presented. The alternative model, Neurological Positivism (NP) - a systems-theoretical evolutionary epistemology - proposes that the measurable energy quality of the algorithmic organization of the Darwinian brain supervenes that of cultural mental models (collectively, mind) and thus downwardly influences the brain circuitry patterns that underlie them. Brain and mind are defined in interrelated energy terms within the context of the self-referential maximum-power principle. The equivalence of maximum-power principle energy hierarchies to chaotic/fractal dynamical designs is described. The production of mental models through reflective thinking is defined as an emergent dimension of energetic self-referencing by the brain operating in accordance with the maximum-power principle. It is concluded that within the context of NP the brain-mind relationship constitutes an "uneven" central state energy identity, with brain supervenient, when brain-mind relative energy qualities are taken into account.
■ Vandervert, Larry R. (Autumn 1991). On the Modeling of Emergent Interaction: Which Will it Be, The Laws of Thermodynamics, or Sperry's "Wheel" in the Subcircuitry? The Journal of Mind and Behavior 12(4): 535-540, ISSN 0271-0137.
Weaknesses in Roger Sperry's "Defense of Mentalism" that appeared in the Spring issue of JMB are described. Sperry's clarification of his mentalist position still appears to lack a plausible mechanism of interaction. The wheel rolling down hill analogy is described as "a ghost in the subcircuitry." Neurological Positivism's (NP) energetic mechanism of brain-mind interaction is summarized. The relatioship of systems theory to reductionism is described briefly in terms of NP.
◈ Vandervert, Larry R. (1995). Chaos theory and the evolution of consciousness and mind: a thermodynamic-holographic resolution to the mind-body problem. New Ideas in Psychology 13(2): 107-127.
▣ Van Eck, Dingmar, Huib Looren de Jong and Maurice M.K.D. Schouten (2006). Evaluating New Wave Reductionism: the case of vision. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57(1): 167-196.
This paper inquires into the nature of intertheoretic relations between psychology and neuroscience. This relationship has been characterized by some as one in which psychological explanations eventually will fall away as otiose, overthrown completely by neurobiological ones. Against this view it will be argued that it squares poorly with scientific practices and empirical developments in the cognitive neurosciences. We analyse a case from research on visual perception, which suggests a much more subtle and complex interplay between psychology and neuroscience than a complete take-over of the former by the latter. In the case of vision, cross-theory influences between psychology and neuroscience go back and forth, resulting in refinement in both disciplines.
We interpret this case study as showing that:
(1) Mutual co-evolution of psychological and neurobiological theories, exemplifying persisting top-down influences from psychology, is a more empirically adequate way to describe psychoneural theory relations than a view on co-evolution, favoured by reductionists, which regards the cross-theory contributions from psychology as merely heuristically useful with no enduring influence on neurobiological theorizing;
(2) In research on vision, discovering (or hypothesizing) the neural basis of functions vindicates psychological approaches, it does not eliminate them;
(3) Current work on vision shows that many perceptual phenomena must be understood in terms of dynamical interactions between an observer and his/her environment. Therefore, we argue that internalist characterizations of the visual system must be supplemented with externalist accounts that address these reciprocal observer-environment interactions involved in vision. Such processes seem quite different from (internal) cellular and molecular ones, and as such seem to lie outside the scope of neuroscientific inquiry. We conclude that psychoneural reduction or elimination is implausible as a meta-theoretical prediction of theory choice in empirical work. Instead, this case study of vision shows that both psychology and neuroscience contribute to, and complement one another in the study of visual perception.
◈ Vaneechoutte, Mario (2000). Experience, awareness and consciousness: Suggestions for definitions as offered by an evolutionary approach. Foundations of Science 5: 429-456.
◈ Van Gulick, Robert (Sep/Oct. 2001). Reduction, Emergence and Other Recent Options on the Mind/Body Problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(9-10): 1-34.
My aim here is to give an overview of the recent philosophic discussion to serve as a map in locating issues and options. I will not offer a comprehensive survey of the debate or mark every important variant to be found in the recent literature. I will mark the principal features of the philosophic landscape that one might use as general orientation points in navigating the terrain.
I will focus in particular on three central and interrelated ideas: those of emergence, reduction, and nonreductive physicalism. The third of these, which has emerged as more or less the majority view among current philosophers of mind, combines a pluralist view about the diversity of what needs to be explained by science with an underlying metaphysical commitment to the physical as the ultimate basis of all that is real. The view has been challenged from both left and right, on one side from dualists (Chalmers, 1996) and on the other from hard core reductive materialists (Kim, 1989). Despite their differences, those critics agree in finding nonreductive physicalism an unacceptable and perhaps even incoherent position. They agree as well in treating reducibility as the essential criterion for physicality; they differ only about whether the criterion can be met. Reductive physicalists argue that it can, and dualists deny it.
The terms ‘reduction’, ‘nonreductive’ and ‘emergence’ get used in a bewildering variety of ways in the mind–body literature, none of which is uniquely privileged or standard. Thus clarity about one’s intended meaning is crucial to avoid confusion and merely verbal disagreements. Thus, much of my mapping will be devoted to sorting out the main versions of reduction and emergence before turning to assess their interrelations and plausibility. My intent is to act largely as a guide and not an advocate. Though I am sure my biases will sometimes affect how I describe the issues, my goal is to lay out the logical geography in a more-or-less neutral way.
◈ Varela, Francisco J. (1991). Organism: A Meshwork of Selfless Selves. In Alfred I. Tauber (ed.) Organism and the Origins of Self. The Hague: Kluwer, pp. 79-107.
◇ Varela, Francisco J. (1995). Resonant cell assemblies: A new approach to cognitive function and neuronal synchrony, Biological Research 28(1): 81–95.
Abstract: This paper presents a novel reading of ideas on temporal binding as a key for cognitive operations by means of fast (gamma band) phase synchrony. We advocate a view of binding of widely distributed cell assemblies transiently locked in a neural hypergraph which serves as a reference point to incorporate or interpret other less coherent concurrent neural events. The paper traces in some detail the empirical evidence concerning the gamma binding process and presents some implications for the constitution of a unified cognitive-mental space.
Author Keywords: Cell assemblies; Cognitive operations; Gamma binding; Neural hypergraph; Phase synchrony
◈ Varela, Francisco J. (1997). Patterns of life: Intertwining identity and cognition. Brain and Cognition 34: 72-87.
◈ Varela, Francisco J., Jean-Philippe Lachaux, Eugenio Rodrigues and Jacques Martinerie (Apr. 2001). The brain web: Phase synchronization and large-scale integration. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 2(4): 229-239.
Abstract: The emergence of a unified cognitive moment relies on the coordination of scattered mosaics of functionally specialized brain regions. Here we review the mechanisms of large-scale integration that counterbalance the distributed anatomical and functional organization of brain activity to enable the emergence of coherent behaviour and cognition. Although the mechanisms involved in large-scale integration are still largely unknown, we argue that the most plausible candidate is the formation of dynamic links mediated by synchrony over multiple frequency bands.
◈ Varela, Francisco J., Evan T. Thompson (2003). Neural synchrony and the unity of mind: A neurophenomenological perspective. In Axel Cleeremans ed. The Unity of Consciousness: Binding, Integration, and Dissociation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
◈ Varela, Francisco J. and Evan T. Thompson and Eleanor Rosch (1991). The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press.
◈ Velmans, Max and Susan Schneider (eds.) (2007). The Blackwell Companion to Conscoiusness. Blackwell Publishing.
◈ Vicente, Agustín (Agostos 2002). The dual Explanandum strategy. CRÍTICA, Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía Vol. 34, No. 101: 73–96.
http://critica.filosoficas.unam.mx/pdf/C101/C101_vicente.pdf
Abstract: In this paper I try to fix the price that a non-epiphenomenal dualism demands. To begin with, the defender of non-epiphenomenal dualism cannot hold that mental events cause physical events, since the physical world is causally closed. Hence, she must say that mental events cause events that are not physical, or at least, events that are not affected by the principle of the causal closure of the physical world (this is the "dual explanandum strategy"). However, this is not all: the events mental causes bring about must fulfill certain further conditions, which I spell out. When properly analyzed, it will be seen that these conditions make the dual explanandum strategy highly demanding.
Keywords: mental causation, dual explanandum strategy, conceptual divides, dualism
◈ Vicente, Agustín (Aug. 2004). The overdetermination argument revisited. Minds and Machines 14(3): 331-347.
Abstract: In this paper I discuss a famous argument for physicalism – which some authors indeed regard as the only argument for it – the overdetermination argument . In fact it is an argument that does not establish that all the entities in the world are physical, but that all those events that enter into causal transactions with the physical world are physical. As mental events seem to cause changes in the physical world, the mind is one of those things that fall within the scope of the argument. Here I analyze one response to the overdetermination argument that has acquired some popularity lately, and which consists in saying that what mental events cause are not physical effects. I try to show that recent attempts to develop this response are not successful, but that there may be a coherent way of doing so. I also try to show that there seems to be a philosophical niche in which this way might fit.
Keywords: dual explanandum strategy - mental causation - overdetermination argument - physicalism
◈ Vicente, Agustín (July 2006). On the causal completeness of physics. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 20(2): 149-171.
Abstract: According to an increasing number of authors, the best, if not the only, argument in favour of physicalism is the so-called ‘overdetermination argument’. This argument, if sound, establishes that all the entities that enter into causal interactions with the physical world are physical. One key premise in the overdetermination argument is the principle of the causal closure of the physical world, said to be supported by contemporary physics. In this paper, I examine various ways in which physics may support the principle, either as a methodological guide or as depending on some other laws and principles of physics.
◈ Voneida, Theodore J. (1998). Sperry's concept of mind as an emergent property of brain function and its implications for the future of humankind. Neuropsychologia 36(10): 1077-1082.
◇ Walter, Sven and Heinz-Dieter Heckmann (eds.) (2003). Physicalism and Mental Causation: The Metaphysics of Mind and Action. Thoverton: Imprint Academic.
Preface
http://www.imprint.co.uk/books/walter.html
◈ Wautischer, Helmut (ed.) (Nov. 2007). Ontology of Consciousness: Percipient Action. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
◈ Weber, Andreas, Francisco J. Varela (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 97-125.
◈ Weber, Bruce H. (July 2003). Emergence of Mind and the Baldwin Effect. In Bruce H. Weber and David J. Depew eds. Evolution and Learning: The Baldwin Effect Reconsidered. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
◈ Weinberg, Steven (Feb. 11, 1988). Reply to "The limits of reductionism" by Ernst Mayr. Nature 331: 475-476.
◈ Welshon, Rex (Mar. 2002). Emergence, supervenience, and Realization. Philosophical Studies 108(1-2): 39-51.
Abstract: In the first section of this paper, I articulate Jaegwon Kim's argument against emergent down ward causation. In the second section, I canvas four responses to Kim's argument and argue that each fails. In the third section, I show that emergent downward causation does not, contra Kim, entail overdetermination. I argue that supervenience of emergent upon base properties is not sufficient for nomological causal relationsbetween emergent and base properties. What sustains Kim's argument is rather the claim that emergent properties realized by base properties can have no causal powers distinct from those base properties. I argue that this is false.
◈ Whittle, Ann (Mar. 2007). The co-instantiation thesis. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85(1): 61-79.
Abstract: The co-instantiation thesis is pivotal to a significant solution to the problem of causal exclusion. But this thesis has been subject to some powerful objections. In this paper, I argue that these difficulties arise because the thesis lacks the necessary metaphysical framework in which its claims should be interpreted and understood. Once this framework is in place, we see that the co-instantiation thesis can answer its critics. The result is a rehabilitated co-instantiation solution to the troubling problem of causal exclusion. But questions remain concerning the viability of certain of its applications.
◈ Wilken, Patrick, Timothy Bayne and Axel Cleeremans (eds.) (forthcoming). The Oxford Companion to Consciousness. Oxford University Press.
◈ Wilson, Robert A. (2001). Two views of realization. Philosophical Studies 104: 1-31.
▣ Wimsatt, William C. (1976). Reductionism, levels of organization and the mind-body problem. In: Gordon G. Globus, Grover Maxwell and Irwin Savodnik (eds.) Consciousness and the Brain: A Scientific and Philosophical Inquiry. New York: Plenum Press, pp. 199-267.
▣ Wimsatt, William C. (1979). Reduction and reductionism. In: P.D. Asquith and H.E. Kyburg Jr. (eds.) (1979). Current Research in the Philosophy of Science. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 352-377.
▣ Wimsatt, William C. (1994). The ontology of complex systems: Levels, perspectives, and causal thickets. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Vol. 20. Calgary: University of Calgary Press.
◈ Wimsatt, William C. (Dec. 1997). Aggregativity: Reductive heuristics for finding emergence. Philosophy of Science 64 (Supplement. Proceedings of the 1996 Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part II: Symposia Papers): S372-S384.
Abstract: Most philosophical accounts of emergence are incompatible with reduction. Most scientists regard a system property as emergent relative to properties of the system's parts if it depends upon their mode of organization―a view consistent with reduction. Emergence can be analyzed as a failure of aggregativity―a state in which "the whole is nothing more than the sum of its parts." Aggregativity requires four conditions, giving tools for analyzing modes of organization. Differently met for different decompositions of the system, and in different degrees, these conditions provide powerful evaluation criteria for choosing decompositions, and heuristics for detecting biases of vulgar reductionisms. This analysis of emergence is compatible with reduction.
◈ Wimsatt, William C. (Sep. 2000). Emergence as non-aggregativity and the biases of reductionisms. Foundations of Science 5(3): 269-297.
Abstract: Most philosophical accounts of emergence are incompatible with reduction. Most scientists regard a system property as emergent relative to properties of its parts if it depends upon their mode of organization-a view consistent with reduction. Emergence is a failure of aggregativity, in which ``the whole is nothing more than the sum of its parts''. Aggregativity requires four conditions, giving powerful tools for analyzing modes of organization. Differently met for different decompositions of the system, and in different degrees, the structural conditions can provide evaluation criteria for choosing decompositions, ``natural kinds'', and detecting functional localization fallacies, approximations, and various biases of vulgar reductionisms. This analysis of emergence and use of these conditions as heuristics is consistent with a broader reductionistic methodology.
Keywords: additivity - aggregativity - emergence - functional localization fallacies - heuristics - near-decomposeability - reduction - whole-parts relations
◈ Witmer, Gene (1999). Supervenience Physicalism and the Problem of Extras. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 37: 315-331.
◇ Wong, Hong Yu (July 2006). Emergents from Fusion. Philosophy of Science 73(3): 345-367.
Received January 2004; revised November 2006. (online date May 17, 2007).
Abstract: This is a critical discussion of Paul Humphreys's fusion view of emergence, focusing on the basal loss feature of his ontology. The discussion yields some general morals for special science ontology.
■ Woolley, R.G. (Apr. 1998). Is there a quantum definition of a molecule? Journal of Mathematical Chemistry 23(1-2): 3–12. (doi:10.1023/A:1019144518901)
◈ Worley, Sara (1997). Determination and Mental causation. Erkenntnis 46: 281-304.
■ Wynn, M. (1999). Emergent phenomena and theistic explanation. International Philosophical Quarterly 39: 141-55.
▣ Yablo, Stephen (Apr. 1992). Mental Causation. Philosophical Review 101(2): 245–280.
◈ Yoo, Julie (Mar. 2007). Mental causation. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
http://www.iep.utm.edu/m/mental-c.htm
◈ Yoshimi, Jeffrey (2007). Supervenience, determination, and dependence. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88(1): 114–133. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0114.2007.00283.x
Issue online: 20 Feb 2007
Abstract: I show how existing concepts of supervenience relate to two more fundamental ontological relations: determination and dependence. Determination says that the supervenient properties of a thing are a function of its base properties, while dependence says that having a supervenient property implies having a base property. I show that most varieties of supervenience are either determination relations or determination relations conjoined with dependence relations. In the process of unpacking these connections I identify limitations of existing concepts of supervenience and provide ways of overcoming them. What results is a more precise, flexible, and powerful set of tools for relating sets of properties than current concepts of supervenience provide. I apply these tools to a recalcitrant problem in the physicalism literature – the problem of extras.
◈ Zelazo, Philip David, Morris Moscovitch and Evan T. Thompson (eds.) (2007). The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness. Cambridge University Press.
◈ Zohar, Danah (Nov. 1995). A quantum mechanical model of consciousness and the emergence of ‘I’. Minds and Machines 5(4): 597-607.
Key words: Quantum - consciousness - emergence - Bose-Einstein condensates - Fröhlich
===========================================================
①지금 2007. 03. 25. 일요일. 흐린 듯. 새벽 03시 16분. 여기는 스타워즈 피시방...
②지금 2007. 03. 26. 월요일. 흐린 듯. 낮 11시 16분. 스타워즈 피시방... 자료 보태다.
③지금 2007. 03. 27. 화요일. 흐림. 낮 1시 01분. 스타워즈 피시방에서 자료 더 보태다.
④지금 2007. 04. 01. 일요일. 조금 흐린 듯. 새벽 06시 10분. 스타워즈 피시방에서... 몇 개의 오타 수정하고 자료를 더 보태다.
⑤지금 2007. 04. 10. 화요일. 10:17. 스타워즈 피시방에서...
⑥지금 2007. 04. 13. 금요일. 새벽부터 가랑비 조금씩 오락가락. 바람 조금. 대부분 흐림. 여기는 ㅊㅈ대 도서관 2층 인터넷 검색대... 논문 입수하러 오다.
⑦지금 2007. 04. 16. 월요일. 06:30. 어제 밤 늦게부터 비. 인력시장에 나가기 직전에 스타워즈 피시방에서 자료 약간 덧붙임.
⑧지금 2007. 04. 17. 화요일. 01:59. 구름이 걷히고 있다. 스타워즈 피시방에서 자료 덧붙임.
⑨지금 2007. 04. 18. 수요일. 22:35. 맑고 따스한 날. 오늘 오창과학산업단지로 땅파기 일 나갔다가(8백원 벌었다), 돌아오는 길에 ㅊㅈ대 도서관에 들러, 오타 수정하고 자료 더 보태다.
⑩지금 2007. 04. 22. 일요일. 22:39. 구름 조금. 오늘 일 나가지 못해, ㅊㅈ대 도서관으로 와서 논문 서지 사항 덧붙이다.
⑪지금 2007. 04. 24. 화요일. 00:40. 맑음. 어제 낮 1시30분~5시 57분까지 시민 컴퓨터 교실에서, 밤 7시 25분~8시 27분까지 ㅊㅂ대 도서관에서, 어제 밤 9시 35분~ 오늘 00시 44분까지 스타워즈 피시방에서 서지 사항을 더 보태다.
⑫지금 2007. 04. 26. 목요일. 06:23. 맑음. 인력시장으로 가기 전에 스타워즈 피시방에서 서지 사항 더 보태다.
(13) 지금 2007. 04. 30. 월요일. 01:12. 맑음. 요즘 산남동 아파트 단지(대우 푸르지오, 대원 칸타빌)에서 베란다 철거 일 하다. 일하고 와서 서지 사항 더 보태고, 몇 가지 표기 잘못을 고치다.
(14) 지금 2007. 05. 05. 토요일. 21:36. 맑음. 오늘 낮 12시쯤에 ㅊㅈ대 도서관으로 와서 서지 사항을 보태다.
(15) 지금 2007. 05. 06. 일요일. 21:33. 흐림. 일 나가지 못해 낮 12시쯤 ㅊㅈ대 도서관으로 와서 서지 사항을 보태다.
(16) 지금 2007. 05. 08. 화요일. 18:05. 맑음. 시민 컴퓨터 교실→ㅊㅂ대 전자정보실→신학생회관→스타워즈 피시방으로 옮겨가며 서지 사항을 보태다. 오늘 수동에서 장롱, 서랍장, 쌀통, 책장을 옮겨주는 일을 하고 3백원 벌다. 일거리는 엄청 많이 들어왔지만, 어쩌다가 나는 마지막으로 가까스로 일을 나갈 수 있었다. 품값이 하루치 기본 벌이의 절반도 안 되는 일거리였다. 하지만, 아주 짧은 시간 동안 일하고 끝냈기 때문에 돈대신 "시간을 많이 벌어" 그런 대로 기분은 좋았다.
(17) 지금 2007. 05. 09. 수요일. 02:42. 조금 흐린 듯. 스타워즈 피시방에서...
(18) 지금 2007. 05. 11. 금요일. 01:58. 맑음. 어제 서울 영풍문고, 반디앤루니스, 교보문고에 다녀오다(낮 1시~밤11시 50분). 서울 공화국 사람들... 풍족하니 잘들 사는 것 같다. 스타워즈 피시방에서...
(19) 지금 2007. 05. 12. 토요일. 03:00. 흐림. 어제(15:40~18:00) 시민 컴퓨터 교실에서, 그리고 스타워즈 피시방에서(22:57~) 서지 목록을 보태다.
(20) 지금 2007. 05. 13. 일요일. 06:21. 맑은 듯. 스타워즈 피시방에서 서지 목록을 보태다.
(21) 지금 2007. 05. 15. 화요일. 16:32. 맑은 듯. 스타워즈 피시방에서 서지 사항을 보태다.
(22) 지금 2007. 05. 18. 금요일. 22:21. 맑음→늦은 낮 5시쯤 넘어서 빗방울 조금 뿌림. 동생네 집에서 자료 조금 보탬. 오늘 봉명동 상가 건물 1층에서 폐업한 가게의 내부 장식(목조)을 철거하는 일을 하다.
(23) 지금 2007. 05. 19. 토요일. 아침에 흐림. 구름이 많은 날. 지금 20:20. 여기는 ㅊㅂ대 신학생회관 1층 검색대. 오늘은 공치다. 이곳으로 와서 서지 사항을 늘리다.
(24) 지금 2007. 05. 20. 일요일. 23:01.
(25) 지금 2007. 05. 22. 화요일. 02:56. 맑음. 신학생회관, 스타워즈 피시방에서...
콸리아/콸리어/퀄리아qualia
첫댓글 와 대단합니다. 이 저작들을 모두 소장하고 계신건가요? 개인적으로 이 의견이 마음에 드네요. There are two sorts of philosophical analysis of emergence. Ontological analyses ground emergence in real, distinct, emergent properties. Epistemological analyses deny emergent properties and stress instead facts about our epistemic status. I review a standard worry for ontological analyses of emergence, that they entail a surfeit of metaphysics, and find that it can easily be sidestepped. I go on to present a new worry, that ontological emergentism entails a highly implausible ontology, which is harder
for the ontological emergentist to avoid.
아래 자료를 다 소장하려면, 돈으로만 따져도 한 1천 만원 정도는 최소한 들지 않겠어요? ^^ 그리고 이 논문들과 책들을 입수하는 데는 시간도 엄청나게 많이 들겠죠. 발품도 엄청 팔아야 되겠죠. (한국스런 상황에서는) 도서관 직원들과 싸움도(!) 많이 해야 할 겁니다^^ 그러나 돈보다 머리/뇌가 더 문제겠죠^^ 저뿐만 아니라 이 자료를 보시는 분들 중 어떤 분이라도, 창발/마음/의식 논문 한 편이라도 써 낸다면, 그보다 더 보람찬 일이 없을 겁니다.
빠삐용 님, 위 인용문이 마음에 든다고 하셨는데, 그럼 창발(적 존재자)에 대해서 회의하신다는 건가요?
Heard, Daniel (2006). A new problem for ontological emergence <--요거이 함 구해서 읽어보고 말씀드릴게요. 저도 아직 생각이 정리된 건 아니라서요. 혹시 가지고 계시면 부탁드립니다.
대니얼 허드의「존재론적 창발의 새로운 문제」Heard, Daniel (Jan. 2006). A new problem for ontological emergence. The Philosophical Quarterly 56(222): 55-62는 이곳 자료실에 저장해 놨습니다. 그리고 이 논문은 블랙웰 출판사에서 무료로 제공하고 있더군요. http://www.blackwell-synergy.com/toc/phiq/56/222 여기로찾아가시면 문서를 공짜로 구할 수 있습니다. 고맙습니다~
와~ 대단해요~많은 분들에게 도움이 될 듯~~^^
저도 부탁 하나 할게요. Buzsaki, Gyorgy (2007). The structure of consciousness. Nature 446: 267-267 (Issue of 15 Mar 2007). Smith, Kerri (2007). Looking for hidden signs of consciousness. Nature 446(7134): 355 (Issue of 22 March 2007).《네이처Nature》지에 실린 위의 두 편의 글을 입수할 수 없을까요? 《네이처Nature》지에 접근 가능하신 분 도와 주세요~~~^^
감사합니다. 저도 학교에 있는 칭구 통해 구했어요. ^^
몇 개의 오타를 수정하고, 자료를 더 보탰습니다. 시간이 모자라 안타깝네요. 다음에 또 추가 자료를 보태고, 앞으로 서지 사항을 더 정확하고 더 완벽하게 작성하겠습니다. 고맙습니다.
Alwyn Scott의 책이 하나 국내에 번역되어 나와있습니다. <마음에 이르는 계단-새로운 의식의 과학에 대한 논쟁> 안창림 백은경 역, 이화여자대학교출판부, 2001. 원제: Stairway to the Mind: The Controversial New Science of Consciousness. 참고가 되었으면 좋겠습니다.
빠삐용 님, 책 소개 고맙습니다. 사실은 저도 얼윈 스캇(스콧)Alwyn Scott의 <마음에 이르는 계단>을 오래 전에 읽어더랬습니다. 제9장 "의식의 창발적 이론을 향하여"라는 흥미로운 부분이 있어서 더욱 관심이 갔었죠. 그런데요 제 생각에, 번역 상태는 그다지 좋지 않다고 봅니다. 언젠가 간단히 분석하고 비판할 생각입니다. 아무튼 서지 목록에 넣어야 할 좋은 책임에는 틀림없습니다. 도움 말씀 정말 고맙습니다.
빠삐용 님, 대니엘 허드의 논문 내용을 요약 정리해서 아래에 올려 놓았습니다. 위에서 빠삐용 님한테 드렸던 간단한 질문에 대한 답을 듣고 싶은데, 가능한 것인지요?